I’m pretty interested in linguistics so after reading gavintaylor’s comment which you linked to, I decided to read part of David Fleck’s doctoral thesis from 2003 on the Matsés language. For distinguishing levels of certainty, Matsés has a particle ada/-da and a verb suffix -chit which mean something like “perhaps” and another particle, ba, that means something like “I doubt that...”, and English speakers already naturally express these distinctions of certainty. Something distinctive that Matsés speakers do though is that they always mark statements about the past with an evidentiality suffix to show whether the proposition is known by direct experience, inference, or conjecture. By the way, it is not true that Matsés “obliges the speakers to indicate the certainty of information provided in a sentence”.
The constructed language Lojban has a richer set of evidentials, derived from a variety of American Indian languages. It might be useful to think about including phrases like these in one’s writing.
These words are based on logarithmic probability, which I don’t really understand. I personally would find it a lot easier to just write a linear probability or percentage such as 80% confidence. It might be useful to include subjective probabilities for various sentences in a document, like Technicalities used to do according to their comment on this post, although they later quit.
Matses language evidentials and epistemic modality
Here, I’ve summarized and quoted key relevant sections from the Fleck’s thesis which are relevant to our discussion of epistemic certainty. It’s possible that there are important parts of Fleck’s thesis that I’ve missed.
The remainder of this post is fairly long, so if you’re not interested in learning more about Matses, don’t feel like you have to read this.
5.5.10 Derivational Suffix -chit ‘Uncertainty’ (page 388, page 410 in the PDF):
This suffix expresses uncertainty, and cannot be used with the uncertainty particle ada/-da. Some example sentences:
It is possibly in tree cavities that the porcupine gives birth.
But others probably drink mashed fruit drink.
Perhaps he died.
5.6.1 Past tenses and evidentiality—page 397 (page 419 in the PDF):
Evidential devices in languages often code multiple types of information with respect to the reliability of the information being related by the speaker. These include: i) source of knowledge (e.g., hearsay); ii) degree of precision or truth, iii) probability of the information being true, and iv) the speaker’s expectations concerning the probability of the statement.
What is different about Matses is that it code evidentiality (source of knowledge) in one set of verbal inflectional suffixes, and epistemic modality (certainty/validation/commitment to truth of statement) by various other means, such as a verbal suffix that comprises a different position class, an uncertainty particle, and a dubitative particle (inflectional suffixes only code uncertainty in nonpast and future tenses). Thus, there is no need for Matses speakers to extend the function of evidentials to code epistemic modality because there are other markers that do this, which are outside the Matses evidential system. (page 398, 420 in the PDF)
Evidentiality is coded only in verbal suffixes that also mark past tense. Nine different tense-evidentiality inflectional suffixes mark a combination of one of three evidential distinctions (direct experience, inference, and conjecture) and one of three past tense distinctions (recent past, distant past and remote past). There are no past tense inflections besides these nine suffixes, so every time a speaker reports a past event, he must reveal the source of knowledge. This contrasts with epistemic modality, which is not an obligatory category in any tense (e.g., the absence of -chit ‘Uncertainty’ does not necessarily imply certainty; section 5.5.10). There is no morphological means of marking hearsay—it must be reported via direct quotation with the quotative verb inflected with one of the nine tense-evidentiality suffixes. Mythical and historical past is marked with the recent past inferential suffix, often reported in a quotative sentence.
Experiential suffixes
The three experiential suffixes are:
-o ‘Recent Past: Experiential’: immediate past to about one month ago
-onda ‘Distant Past: Experiential’: about one month to about 50 years ago
-denne ‘Remote Past: Experiential’: about 50 to about 100 years ago (approximate maximum human life span)
experiential refers to a situation where the speaker detects the occurrence of an event at the time that it transpires (or a state at the time that it holds true).
Inferential suffixes
The four inferential suffixes are (page 406, page 428 in the PDF):
-ac ‘Recent Past: Inferential’: immediate past to about one month ago
-nëdac ‘Distant Past: Inferential’: about one month ago to speaker’s infancy
-ampic ‘Remote Past: Inferential’: before speaker’s infancy
-nëdampic ‘Remote Past: Inferential’: before speaker’s infancy. It’s unclear if this differs from -ampic or is used for events even further in the past.
Some examples of inferential statements (page 406, 428 in the PDF):
Davy (evidently) left to go to sleep.
Davy (evidently) left, probably because he got bored.
with first-person forms, narrative and mythical past, ancient habitual activities, etc., where evidential distinctions are difficult or not relevant, inferential suffixes are used as a default. (page 424, page 446 in the PDF)
Conjecture suffixes
The two conjecture suffixes are (page 417, page 439 in the PDF):
-ash ‘Recent Past Conjecture’: immediate past to about one month ago
-nëdash ‘Distant Past Conjecture’: more than about one month ago
What is meant by “conjecture” here is that the speaker wishes to report the occurrence of an event or state that he did not witness, did not hear about from somebody else, and for which there is no resulting evidence. For example, if a dog is missing, the owner might conjecture that a snake bit it or a jaguar ate it.
Examples of conjectural statements:
Davy probably slept.
I suppose Davy got bored.
History/mythology
Statements about history/mythology from the “inaccessible past” use the suffix (-pa)-ac (cadennec) (page 424, page 446 in the PDF).
Hearsay
Hearsay is marked by a direct quote + quotative (ca or que) + any experiential or conjecture suffix (page 424, page 446 in the PDF).
9.4 Clause-level particles—page 724 (page 745 in the PDF):
ada/-da: a clause-level particle to express uncertainty. E.g., “I doubt if you’re going to come here”.
ba: a clause-level particle to express doubt. E.g., “ada debi cho-pa-ash ba” “I’m not sure if Davy has arrived.”
I’m pretty interested in linguistics so after reading gavintaylor’s comment which you linked to, I decided to read part of David Fleck’s doctoral thesis from 2003 on the Matsés language. For distinguishing levels of certainty, Matsés has a particle ada/-da and a verb suffix -chit which mean something like “perhaps” and another particle, ba, that means something like “I doubt that...”, and English speakers already naturally express these distinctions of certainty. Something distinctive that Matsés speakers do though is that they always mark statements about the past with an evidentiality suffix to show whether the proposition is known by direct experience, inference, or conjecture. By the way, it is not true that Matsés “obliges the speakers to indicate the certainty of information provided in a sentence”.
The constructed language Lojban has a richer set of evidentials, derived from a variety of American Indian languages. It might be useful to think about including phrases like these in one’s writing.
ja’o [jalge] I conclude
ca’e I define
ba’a [balvi] I expect I experience I remember
su’a [sucta] I generalize I particularize
ti’e [tirna] I hear (hearsay)
ka’u [kulnu] I know by cultural means
se’o [senva] I know by internal experience
za’a [zgana] I observe
pe’i [pensi] I opine
ru’a [sruma] I postulate
ju’a [jufra] I state
DataPacRat from Less Wrong proposed Lojban particles to express subjective probabilities:
ni’uci’ibei’e: 0%
ni’upabei’e: 44.3%
ni’ubei’e: <50%
nobei’e: 50%
ma’ubei’e: >50%
pabei’e: 55.7%
etc.
ci’ibei’e: 100%
xobei’e: asking listener their level of belief
These words are based on logarithmic probability, which I don’t really understand. I personally would find it a lot easier to just write a linear probability or percentage such as 80% confidence. It might be useful to include subjective probabilities for various sentences in a document, like Technicalities used to do according to their comment on this post, although they later quit.
Matses language evidentials and epistemic modality
Here, I’ve summarized and quoted key relevant sections from the Fleck’s thesis which are relevant to our discussion of epistemic certainty. It’s possible that there are important parts of Fleck’s thesis that I’ve missed.
There’s also a more recent paper by Fleck from 2007 specifically focusing on evidentials: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40070903. I haven’t read this.
The remainder of this post is fairly long, so if you’re not interested in learning more about Matses, don’t feel like you have to read this.
5.5.10 Derivational Suffix -chit ‘Uncertainty’ (page 388, page 410 in the PDF):
This suffix expresses uncertainty, and cannot be used with the uncertainty particle ada/-da. Some example sentences:
It is possibly in tree cavities that the porcupine gives birth.
But others probably drink mashed fruit drink.
Perhaps he died.
5.6.1 Past tenses and evidentiality—page 397 (page 419 in the PDF):
Experiential suffixes
The three experiential suffixes are:
-o ‘Recent Past: Experiential’: immediate past to about one month ago
-onda ‘Distant Past: Experiential’: about one month to about 50 years ago
-denne ‘Remote Past: Experiential’: about 50 to about 100 years ago (approximate maximum human life span)
Inferential suffixes
The four inferential suffixes are (page 406, page 428 in the PDF):
-ac ‘Recent Past: Inferential’: immediate past to about one month ago
-nëdac ‘Distant Past: Inferential’: about one month ago to speaker’s infancy
-ampic ‘Remote Past: Inferential’: before speaker’s infancy
-nëdampic ‘Remote Past: Inferential’: before speaker’s infancy. It’s unclear if this differs from -ampic or is used for events even further in the past.
Some examples of inferential statements (page 406, 428 in the PDF):
Davy (evidently) left to go to sleep.
Davy (evidently) left, probably because he got bored.
Conjecture suffixes
The two conjecture suffixes are (page 417, page 439 in the PDF):
-ash ‘Recent Past Conjecture’: immediate past to about one month ago
-nëdash ‘Distant Past Conjecture’: more than about one month ago
Examples of conjectural statements:
Davy probably slept.
I suppose Davy got bored.
History/mythology
Statements about history/mythology from the “inaccessible past” use the suffix (-pa)-ac (cadennec) (page 424, page 446 in the PDF).
Hearsay
Hearsay is marked by a direct quote + quotative (ca or que) + any experiential or conjecture suffix (page 424, page 446 in the PDF).
9.4 Clause-level particles—page 724 (page 745 in the PDF):
ada/-da: a clause-level particle to express uncertainty. E.g., “I doubt if you’re going to come here”.
ba: a clause-level particle to express doubt. E.g., “ada debi cho-pa-ash ba” “I’m not sure if Davy has arrived.”
You blew my mind, thanks!