Thatâs all assuming neartermism, right? I agree that neartermism plausibly entails prioritizing non-human animals. But neartermism seems very arbitrary, and should plausibly not receive nearly as much weight as GHD currently receives in OPâs portfolio.*
Rather, my suggestion was that the current explicitly âlongtermistâ bucket should be thought of as something like âhighly speculative longtermismâ, and the current GHD bucket should be thought of as something like âimproving the long-term via robustly good methodsâ.
Itâs harder to see how helping animals would fit that latter description. (Maybe the best case would be the classic Kantian argument that abusing animals less would help make us morally better.)
*: Insofar as the GHD bucket is really just motivated by something like âsticking close to common senseâ, and people started using âneartermismâ as a slightly misnamed label for this, the current proposal to shift to very counterintuitive priorities whilst doubling down on the unprincipled rejection of longtermism seems kind of puzzling to me!
We shouldnât just assume that neartermism is the principled alternative to speculative longtermism, and then stick to that assumption come what may (i.e., even if it leads to the result that we should âmostlyâ ignore poor people). Rather, I think we should be more open-minded about how we should think of the different âbucketsâ in a Worldview-Diversified portfolio, and cautious of completely dismissing common-sense priorities (even as we give significant weight and support to a range of theoretically well-supported counterintuitive cause areas).
Nope, not assuming neartermism. The report has the details. Short version: across a range of decision theories, chickens look really good.
That said, I totallyagree that from a purely conceptual perspective, we should âbe more open-minded about how we should think of the different âbucketsâ in a Worldview-Diversified portfolio, and cautious of completely dismissing common-sense priorities (even as we give significant weight and support to a range of theoretically well-supported counterintuitive cause areas).â
Edit to add: I think you might mean something different by ârobust goodnessâ than what I had in mind. From a quick look at your link, youâre considering a range of different decision theories, risk-weightings, etc., and noting that chickens do at least moderately well on a wide range of theoretical assumptions.
I instead meant to be talking about empirical robustness: roughly, âhelping the long-term via methods that are especially likely to do some immediate good, and with less risk of proving long-term counterproductive.â Or, more concisely, âlongtermism via nearterm goods with positive ripple effectsâ. And then assessing what does best via this particular theoretical standard (to make up one bucket in our portfolio).
Since your report doesnât consider ripple effects, it doesnât address the kind of ârobust longtermismâ bucket I have in mind.
Thatâs all assuming neartermism, right? I agree that neartermism plausibly entails prioritizing non-human animals. But neartermism seems very arbitrary, and should plausibly not receive nearly as much weight as GHD currently receives in OPâs portfolio.*
Rather, my suggestion was that the current explicitly âlongtermistâ bucket should be thought of as something like âhighly speculative longtermismâ, and the current GHD bucket should be thought of as something like âimproving the long-term via robustly good methodsâ.
Itâs harder to see how helping animals would fit that latter description. (Maybe the best case would be the classic Kantian argument that abusing animals less would help make us morally better.)
*: Insofar as the GHD bucket is really just motivated by something like âsticking close to common senseâ, and people started using âneartermismâ as a slightly misnamed label for this, the current proposal to shift to very counterintuitive priorities whilst doubling down on the unprincipled rejection of longtermism seems kind of puzzling to me!
We shouldnât just assume that neartermism is the principled alternative to speculative longtermism, and then stick to that assumption come what may (i.e., even if it leads to the result that we should âmostlyâ ignore poor people). Rather, I think we should be more open-minded about how we should think of the different âbucketsâ in a Worldview-Diversified portfolio, and cautious of completely dismissing common-sense priorities (even as we give significant weight and support to a range of theoretically well-supported counterintuitive cause areas).
Nope, not assuming neartermism. The report has the details. Short version: across a range of decision theories, chickens look really good.
That said, I totally agree that from a purely conceptual perspective, we should âbe more open-minded about how we should think of the different âbucketsâ in a Worldview-Diversified portfolio, and cautious of completely dismissing common-sense priorities (even as we give significant weight and support to a range of theoretically well-supported counterintuitive cause areas).â
Ok, thanks for clarifying!
Edit to add: I think you might mean something different by ârobust goodnessâ than what I had in mind. From a quick look at your link, youâre considering a range of different decision theories, risk-weightings, etc., and noting that chickens do at least moderately well on a wide range of theoretical assumptions.
I instead meant to be talking about empirical robustness: roughly, âhelping the long-term via methods that are especially likely to do some immediate good, and with less risk of proving long-term counterproductive.â Or, more concisely, âlongtermism via nearterm goods with positive ripple effectsâ. And then assessing what does best via this particular theoretical standard (to make up one bucket in our portfolio).
Since your report doesnât consider ripple effects, it doesnât address the kind of ârobust longtermismâ bucket I have in mind.