How to Measure Capacity for Welfare and Moral Status
Executive Summary
An animal’s capacity for welfare is how good or bad its life can go. An animal’s moral status is the degree to which an animal’s experiences or interests matter morally. It’s plausible that animals differ in their capacity for welfare and/or their moral status. These differences could affect the way we ought to allocate resources across interventions and/or cause areas. Unfortunately, measuring capacity for welfare and moral status is tremendously difficult.
When donors or researchers choose to focus on cause areas or interventions that target certain species rather than others, they are often implicitly making judgments about the comparative value of different animals (including humans). Without a model for quantifying differences in comparative value, such judgments are apt to be guided by imperfect and likely unreliable heuristics.
There are two non-exclusive methods we might employ to measure capacity for welfare and moral status. The first method is to survey various experts about what sort of tradeoffs among animals they would endorse. This approach is relatively simple and cheap, but it relies on the assumption that intuitions about moral tradeoffs reliably track the moral truth. This assumption looks dubious. Intuitive judgments of this kind are often sensitive to non-evidential factors. Deep-rooted, widespread speciesism is likely to prejudice responses.
The second method is more time-consuming and complex but potentially more objective. The method proceeds in three steps. The first step is to canvass the relevant philosophical literature to generate a relatively theory-neutral list of characteristics that might contribute to capacity for welfare or moral status. The second step is to find empirically measurable proxies for those characteristics and weight the proxies by their relative importance. The third step is to canvass the relevant scientific literature to score different animals of interest according to the features identified in the second step. Estimates of uncertainty would be made at each step, and a sensitivity analysis would help identify areas of high information value. I estimate that such a project would require between five thousand and seven thousand person-hours to complete.
Introduction and Context
This post is the second in Rethink Priorities’ series about comparing capacity for welfare and moral status across species. The primary goal of this series is to improve the way resources are allocated within the effective animal advocacy movement. A secondary goal is to improve the allocation of resources between human-focused cause areas and nonhuman-animal-focused cause areas. In the first post I lay the conceptual framework for the rest of the series, outlining different theories of welfare and moral status and the relationship between the two. In this, the second entry in the series, I present and evaluate two methodologies for measuring and comparing capacity for welfare and moral status. In the third entry in the series, I examine temporal perception as a case study of a morally important feature that can plausibly be measured and compared across species. In later entries in the series, I explore the possibility that the experiences of some nonhuman animals are worth more, morally, than the experiences of humans, and I map some future research directions and posit concrete suggestions for making progress in this area.
The Measurement Problem
Humans exploit a huge variety of animals. On an annual basis, humans slaughter about 290 million frogs, 480 million goats, 2.9 billion snails, 3 billion ducks, 22 billion cochineal bugs, 69 billion chickens, 300 billion crustaceans, and nearly a trillion commercially caught fish.[1] At any given time, humans confine about 251 million sheep, 265 million cows, 7.5 billion hens, and more than 1.4 trillion bees to produce wool, milk, eggs, and honey. Counting somewhat conservatively, humans exploit at least 33 orders of animals, across 13 classes and 6 phyla.[2] The effective animal advocacy (EAA) movement has limited resources, and it must choose how to allocate these scarce resources among these different animals, most of whom are treated miserably by humans. Since we can’t (yet) help all these animals, we must decide which animals to prioritize.[3]
In the first entry in this series, I argued that there are good reasons to think that animals differ in their capacity for welfare and/or their moral status. I also claimed that these differences could significantly affect the way we ought to allocate resources across cause areas and interventions. Of course, these differences can only affect our allocative decision-making if we know about them and know, at least roughly, their magnitudes. Hence, it is important that we devise a method for reliably measuring capacity for welfare and moral status and comparing them across species.[4]
Methods for measuring capacity for welfare and moral status can be assessed across a number of important criteria. The method must be valid and accurate—that is, it must actually track capacity for welfare and moral status and be sensitive to differences in capacity for welfare and moral status. Ideally, the method would be applicable across species—that is, it would be accurate and valid with respect to phylogenetically distant animals occupying radically different ecological niches.[5] Ideally, the method would be sensitive to moral uncertainty—that is, rather than assume a particular normative framework, the method would allow one to input a variety of plausible axiological assumptions and observe how changing the assumptions changes the outputs of the final model. The practical feasibility of the method must also be considered. How simple is the method to execute and use when finished? How much would executing the method cost? How likely is it that an attempt to execute the method ends in failure?[6]
In this post I consider two methods for measuring and comparing capacity for welfare and moral status: (1) a holistic approach, in which relevant experts employ their normative and biological expertise to make all-things-considered estimates of the appropriate tradeoffs between different lives, experiences, or interests, and (2) an atomistic approach, in which we identify empirical proxies for morally salient features, then let our best scientific understanding of the degree to which different animals possess those features guide our estimates of comparative moral value. The two approaches are not in principle mutually exclusive. One could in theory adopt both approaches, then let one’s final estimates be conditioned by a weighted reflective equilibrium between the two.
I argue that the atomistic approach is the more difficult but ultimately the more accurate method. Thus, any reflective equilibrium between the two approaches ought to be weighted more heavily toward the atomistic rather than the holistic approach. Nonetheless, the atomistic approach faces serious complications along at least three dimensions: identifying empirically-measurable proxies for the morally salient features, comparing those proxies across phylogenetically distant animals, and incorporating differential performance on those features into a unified, common metric weighted by the importance of the features.
Of course, we shouldn’t expect that we’ll ever be able to pinpoint an animal’s precise capacity for welfare or moral status. As I detail later in this series, there is a tremendous amount of empirical uncertainty about the extent to which different animals display different morally relevant traits and features. And even if the empirical uncertainty could be resolved, the philosophical uncertainty would likely remain.[7] Thus, our best methodology executed as well as we can will still deliver only ranges of values, and it’s difficult to say in advance how wide those ranges will be. Attempting to measure capacity for welfare and moral status will help us identify our degree of uncertainty regarding these issues. Merely knowing the extent of our uncertainty could plausibly improve our decision-making process.[8]
The Holistic Approach
According to what I’m calling the holistic approach to measuring capacity for welfare and moral status, the best way to estimate moral status and capacity for welfare is to think holistically about the comparative value of different sorts of animals. The approach is holistic because it starts at the question we are trying to answer rather than trying to decompose the question into constituent parts. The holistic approach elicits all-things-considered judgments about the relative value of different animals, and there is no underlying framework which determines which considerations ought to bear on the final judgments.
Insofar as there is a currently endorsed method for adjudicating disputes about the comparative value of different animals, the holistic approach seems to be the preferred method. As far as I can tell, in most organizations decisions about the comparative value of different animals are governed by intuitive judgments rather than tables and spreadsheets.[9] This is probably for the best. Capacity for welfare and moral status are complicated topics; they don’t lend themselves to easy formulae. Explicit numerical representations are apt to gloss over important complexity, and simple quantitative models are unlikely to outperform all-things-considered judgments by domain experts. As we’ll see below, I estimate that executing the atomistic approach to the rough specifications I outline would require about six thousand person-hours, with little action-guiding payoff until at least midway through the project. Since most organizations don’t have three to six thousand hours to think about these issues, the holistic approach is an acceptable short-term stopgap. In the medium- to long-term, the only way to ensure that we are efficiently allocating resources across different groups of animals is to invest the time and money necessary to thoroughly study moral status and capacity for welfare.
Tradeoffs and preferences
One way to attempt to measure comparative moral value is by directly judging what sort of tradeoffs between different species would be appropriate. The tradeoffs might be couched in terms of lives: we might wonder how many salmon we ought to be willing to let die in order to save one thousand turkeys. The tradeoffs might be couched in terms of experiences: we might wonder how many minutes of suffering we ought to be willing to let a lobster endure in order to alleviate one hundred minutes of frog suffering. Or the tradeoffs might be couched in terms of interests: assuming pigs and chickens have an equally strong interest in avoiding extreme confinement, we might wonder how many hens we ought to be willing to forgo freeing in order to liberate ten sows.
Another approach is to couch the tradeoffs in terms of what species one would prefer to be. For example, Peter Singer allows that “it would not necessarily be speciesist to rank the value of different lives in some hierarchical ordering. How we should go about doing this is another question, and I have nothing better to offer than the imaginative reconstruction of what it would be like to be a different kind of being” (Singer 2011: 91).[10] He suggests that “If it is true that we can make sense of the choice between existence as a horse and existence as a human, then – whichever way the choice would go – we can make sense of the idea that the life of one kind of animal possesses greater value than the life of another; and if this is so, then the claim that the life of every being has equal value is on very weak ground” (Singer 2011: 91). With a suitably large and diverse sample of matched pairs, we could create an ordered ranking.
We could also ask how many days of one’s human life one would be willing to forgo to experience some duration of time as another species. This approach would allow us to assign cardinal numbers to the value of animal lives. Shelly Kagan imagines such an approach. He writes, “The average human life span is about 79 years, or more than 28,000 days. Divided by ten thousand that’s still more than 2.8 days. If, like me, you wouldn’t give up even a single day as a person for an entire extra lifetime as a fly, then you agree that the welfare to be had within a fly’s life is less than one ten thousandth the welfare to be found in a person’s life” (Kagan 2019: 90, fn 5).[11] Again, by considering one’s preferred tradeoffs across a large and diverse sample of different animals, we could begin to construct a hierarchy of comparative moral value.
Survey data
There is already a wealth of existing survey data about attitudes to animals, and some of this data can be repurposed to infer the general public’s positions on the morally appropriate tradeoffs among species. The Animal Attitudes Scale (AAS) has been in use since 2002.[12] The AAS and its variants[13] ask respondents to agree or disagree (on a five point scale) with twenty-eight statements such as It is morally wrong to hunt wild animals just for sport and Breeding animals for their skins is a legitimate use of animals. Some of the questions refer to specific animals, such as It is morally wrong to eat chicken and fish and A human has no right to use a horse as a means of transportation (riding) or entertainment (racing). Comparing such responses reveals rough differences in attitudes toward different animals, but it does not reveal the degree to which some animals are valued more than others.
A new scale, the Animal Purpose Questionnaire (APQ), has recently been devised to offer “a more differentiated measure of attitudes to animal use across a variety of settings” (Bradley et al 2020: 1). The APQ asks respondents the extent to which they agree (on a five point scale) that it’s permissible for animals to be killed for different purposes. In total the APQ asks about sixteen animals[14] and five uses,[15] though the survey is designed so that respondents aren’t asked about all animals and all uses. Generalizing across respondents and usage categories, Bradley et al. 2020 find that respondents tend to value monkeys, badgers, tree shrews, chimpanzees, dogs, dolphins and parrots more highly than rats, mice, pigs, octopuses, chickens, zebrafish, carp, and pigeons. Again, though, the scale cannot pinpoint the exact extent to which some animals are valued more than others.
Another recent survey, Miralles et al. 2019, asked respondents about their relative levels of empathy and compassion for animals of different species. Each respondent was asked to view pictures of two animals of different species. For the empathy questions, respondents chose the animal for which they felt like they were “better able to understand the feelings or emotions of.” For the compassion questions, respondents chose which animal they would save if both were in danger of death. Both empathy and compassion decreased with increasing phylogenetic distance from humans. However, once again, this survey methodology does not allow us to infer the exact numerical tradeoffs between animals that respondents would endorse.
The general public has occasionally been surveyed about specific tradeoffs. For instance, in March 2019 Scott Alexander ran a small survey (n=50) asking respondents to estimate the relative value of nonhuman animal lives in comparison to a human life. The median respondent in his survey estimated that a single human is as valuable as 4,000 lobsters, 500 chickens, 50 cows, 35 pigs, 7 elephants, or 5 chimpanzees. Shortly thereafter, a commenter called Tibbar attempted to replicate Alexander’s survey with a larger pool of respondents (n=263). The results were strikingly different, with Tibbar’s respondents ranking the relative value of a human life much lower than Alexander’s respondents. According to the median respondent in Tibbar’s survey, a human life is as valuable as 60 lobsters, 25 chickens, 5 pigs, 3 cows, and 2 chimpanzees. (Elephants scored as highly as humans.)
Rethink Priorities offered to investigate the discrepancy between Alexander’s and Tibbar’s results. We launched a new, larger survey (n=490) and found enormous variance in the value assigned to different animals. Many respondents assigned each animal a value equal to humans, and many respondents did essentially the opposite—indicating that human life was incommensurable with or infinitely more valuable than nonhuman animal life. In between these positions there was an extreme range, with some respondents assigning a value to each animal nearly equal with humans and other respondents assigning nonhuman animals quadrillions times lower moral value than a single human. Such variegated data posed many interpretative challenges, but ultimately we concluded there were two natural ways to analyze the data, one of which supported Alexander’s high values and one of which supported Tibbar’s lower figures. Alexander reported on our findings in May 2019. A full write-up from Rethink Priorities is forthcoming.
Such surveys are not limited to popular blogs. For example, in a 2007 phone survey of one thousand Americans, Oklahoma State agricultural economists Bailey Norwood and Jayson Lusk asked respondents to agree or disagree with the following statement: “If a new technology were created that could either eliminate the suffering of 1 human or the suffering of X farm animals, it should be used to eliminate the suffering of the 1 human.” The variable X was randomly set to 1, 10, 50, 100, 500, 1,000, 5,000, or 10,000. Extrapolating from the results, Norwood and Lusk concluded that the average American believes that the suffering of one human is equivalent to the suffering of about 11,500 farm animals.[16]
A more recent survey of this type is reported in Weathers et al. 2020. Respondents were asked to compare the suffering of cows, pigs, and chickens via a series of tradeoff questions. For example, a respondent might be asked to compare two hypothetical programs, the first of which would prevent one thousand cows from contracting an illness that causes rapid death and the second of which would prevent X chickens from contracting a similar illness that causes rapid death. Respondents were then required to select the lowest value of X for which the second program would produce the greater overall reduction in suffering, with possible values for X ranging from one to one million.[17] According to the authors, “Approximately 39.9% of participants valued cattle more than chickens, and a similar proportion (38.8%) valued pigs more than chickens” (Weathers et al. 2020: 4).[18]
Few of these survey designs are ideal and none is perfect. Nevertheless, the data presented here do yield at least one tentative conclusion: many people are comfortable endorsing a hierarchy of moral value. It appears to be a commonly—if not universally—accepted view that some animals are more valuable than others, even if there is disagreement as to the extent of the differences. What remains to be seen is whether or not this position is justified. In the following section, I present some evidence that lay intuitions about comparative moral value should not be trusted.
The problem with appeals to intuition
One initial concern about appeals to intuition in this domain is the general zoological ignorance of the intuiting public. As I noted above, humans directly exploit at least 33 orders of animals across 13 classes and 6 phyla. The average person simply doesn’t know much detail about the lives of, say, goats, geese, carp, catfish, earthworms, silkworms, snails, or squid.[19] But without detailed knowledge of the characteristics of the species under comparison, it’s hard to see what could justify judgments of comparative moral worth. However, I want to set this worry aside. I assume that if we adopted the holistic approach, we would only care to elicit the intuitions of qualified experts.[20] My worry is that even the intuitions of zoological experts will be unreliable.
The holistic approach is driven by all-things-considered judgments about which species one ought to prefer to be and which tradeoffs between species are morally appropriate. By their very nature, the origin of these judgments is somewhat opaque. The judgments are not the product of a clearly delineated algorithm or decision tree. They don’t imply whether variation in moral value is due to differences in moral status or differences in capacity for welfare (or both). They certainly don’t say which particular features are driving the difference in moral value. In many ways this is a feature, not a bug: developing a formula for calculating moral value is difficult, and without rigorous, protracted investigation, such a formula is unlikely to outperform rapid intuitive judgment. But the speed of intuitive judgment comes at a price: when the origin of a judgment is opaque, it’s easier for unwanted influences to creep in without one’s knowledge.[21]
There is already a large literature which demonstrates that uncalibrated intuitions are often sensitive to non-evidential factors.[22] Since intuitions about the comparative moral value of nonhuman animals are not amenable to independent calibration, these intuitions are almost certainly influenced to some degree by factors that are morally irrelevant. So I think there is good reason in general to worry that unwanted considerations unduly sway one’s intuitions about the value of nonhuman animals. To compound this general worry, there are reasons to think that, in the specific case at hand, irrelevant factors are likely to unconsciously taint our reasoning.
There is ample evidence that humans tend to value large mammals, especially those with big eyes or human-like characteristics, over other animals. Animals with fur are preferred to those with scales; animals with two or four limbs are preferred to those with six, eight, or ten limbs. Animals deemed to be aggressive, dirty, or dangerous are perceived negatively. Companion animals and pets attract more sympathy than comparable farmed or wild animals.[23] These factors, and many others, will plausibly influence our reactions to thought experiments.
Consider, for instance, Singer’s invitation to assess whether we would prefer to experience life as one species rather than another. The goal of the exercise is to use our imaginative faculties to estimate the capacity for welfare that different animals possess.[24] In addition to the above biases, such thought experiments may be swayed by personal considerations that have nothing to do with capacity for welfare. Perhaps I would prefer to be a marlin rather than a chimpanzee because I like to swim. Perhaps I would rather be a gecko than a polar bear because I dislike cold climes. Perhaps I’d prefer to be a penguin rather than a snake because I know penguins engender more sympathy than snakes.
Similar concerns haunt Kagan’s invitation to consider how much of one’s human life one would sacrifice to gain an extra lifetime as a member of another species. Perhaps I would gladly sacrifice a year of my human life for an extra lifetime as a sparrow because the novelty of unaided flight intrigues me. Of course, in carefully presenting the thought experiment we would stipulate that such personal preferences are irrelevant and ought to be bracketed when considering the tradeoff. But it’s unclear exactly which personal preferences are irrelevant, and even if we were confident in our delineation of relevant versus irrelevant preferences, it’s an open question how successfully we can bracket the irrelevant influences by stipulation.[25] Moreover, it’s also a bit unclear how Kagan’s thought experiments could tell us much about moral status (as opposed to capacity for welfare). Moral status presumably makes no intrinsic contribution to phenomenology, so if two animals had the same capacity for welfare but different moral statuses, it’s unclear why I should be willing to give up more time for an extra life as the animal with the higher status.
The surveys in the previous section sometimes report results that are best understood if we accept that irrelevant factors often drive our intuitive responses. For instance, in the APQ, respondents typically don’t object to killing mice and rats for medical research, basic science research, or pest control, but respondents do object to them being killed for food production. This is almost certainly because respondents find the idea of eating mice and rats unappealing, which, of course, is totally beside the point (Bradley et al. 2020: 17-18).
Then there is the specter of speciesism, which in simple terms is a prejudice in favor of one’s own species. Jeff Sebo warns that “when we are considering a topic like animal ethics, when our intuitions are so heavily influenced by speciesism and other such biases, there is a risk that focusing narrowly on simple, idealized thought experiments, as Kagan does, will anchor us to an unacceptably conservative and speciesist moral theory” (Sebo 2020: 6). Sebo adds that “we intuitively underestimate the capacities of nonhuman animals for a variety of reasons. We tend to perceive happiness and autonomy more easily in humans than in other animals. Moreover, insofar as there are limits on how happy or autonomous an animal can be, we tend to attribute these limits to internal causes, that is, facts about the animal, rather than to external causes, that is, facts about the conditions in which the animal is living. If we were to correct for these tendencies, then we would likely see less of a divide between humans and other animals than we currently do” (Sebo 2020: 6). Sebo focuses his criticism on comparisons between humans and nonhumans. But what about comparisons restricted only to nonhuman animals?
The belief that humans are more valuable than nonhumans is often a manifestation of speciesism. But the idea that some nonhuman animals are worth more than some other nonhuman animals isn’t obviously speciesist. If I judge that chickens are more valuable than trout, it’s not obvious how such a judgment reflects a prejudice in favor of my own species. Nonetheless, the judgment might still be speciesist if humans are unjustifiably taken to be the standard against which nonhuman animals are compared, even when they are compared against each other. Similarity to humans might be the metric by which most people evaluate the comparative moral value of nonhuman animals, and if that is a speciesist criterion, then the comparisons will be tainted by speciesism.
The Atomistic Approach
All told, I think the above worries suggest that we should search for a more objective approach to measuring comparative moral value. Of course, no approach to measuring comparative moral value will be completely devoid of appeals to intuition and immune to the influence of speciesism. However, by standardizing the inputs to the model and tying those inputs to empirical data, we can make our intuitions explicit and public, the better to judge them. Such a model would hopefully reduce the extent to which we are swayed by non-evidential factors. It would also enable us to pinpoint the differences driving disagreements about judgments of comparative moral value, making such disagreements more productive.
The holistic approach to measuring capacity for welfare and moral status relies on all-things-considered subjective judgments. If such judgments are likely prone to errors that bias the process, we should be wary of the holistic approach. One way to help correct for these biases is to ground our judgments wherever possible in the hard facts of animal physiology, psychology, and ethology.[26] Despite Kagan’s invitation to entertain various thought experiments, he concedes that “any particular judgments we might make about how one type of animal ranks in comparison to others will be subject to revision in light of further advances in empirical science. We may well discover that we have overestimated or underestimated the psychological capacities of any given type of animal. Unsurprisingly, then, any such ranking will remain tentative (and perhaps a bit rough as well). But in principle, at least, a suitably informed ranking could be produced, and that ranking could then be improved upon as science reveals more about the details of animal psychology” (Kagan 2019: 113-114, emphasis added).
The holistic approach begins with questions about the morally appropriate tradeoffs among species. An alternative is to first develop a rough system for adjudicating comparisons of capacity for welfare and moral status. What I’m calling the atomistic approach begins with the question ‘What features and characteristics determine moral status and capacity for welfare?’ then uses the answers to that question to determine the morally appropriate tradeoffs among species. The approach is atomistic because it decomposes the question of comparative moral value into discrete constituents (atoms) that are answered independently and then aggregated. This approach is necessarily more complicated, but the potential gains in accuracy may be worth it. In the following section, I outline what one such strategy for producing a suitably informed ranking might look like.
A rough guide to estimating moral status and capacity for welfare atomistically
Such an approach might proceed in three stages. The first stage would lay the conceptual framework for the project.[27] During this stage, one would specify which features are likely to determine capacity for welfare and moral status.[28] This stage would not require one to take a definitive stance on different theories of welfare and moral status, but it would require one to determine the implications of various plausible views. Because philosophical questions are notoriously difficult to resolve, we should be fairly uncertain about which theories of welfare and moral status are correct. Given this deep uncertainty, we should probably value interventions that are robust across a number of different plausible views. The goal of this stage would be twofold: (1) to generate a relatively theory-neutral list of characteristics that might contribute to capacity for welfare or moral status and (2) to understand the relative importance of the characteristics, weighted both by the importance of the characteristic within a given theory and by the probability that the theory is true.
The second stage would lay the methodological framework for the project. During this stage, one would operationalize the features and characteristics enumerated during the first stage into measurable proxies. This stage would require engagement with the empirical literature so as to know what in practice can be measured. But this stage would also require substantive theoretical reasoning, to judge which metrics are good proxies for the features we ultimately care about. A key goal of this stage would be to find measurable metrics that can be meaningfully compared across phylogenetically distant animals. The metrics must also be comparable in some sense to each other, so that they can be weighted against each other.
The third stage would be the simplest but the most time-intensive. First, we would select the animals to be investigated for the project (including the taxonomic rank at which to compare them). Because the goal of the project is to improve the way resources are allocated across interventions, it makes sense to select animals that humans directly exploit in very large numbers. Next, the relevant scientific literature would be systematically reviewed and organized, and the results compiled in a large database. The end-product might be a table consisting of ~30 features measured across ~30 orders of animals. This template provides an example framework.[29] (Note that the taxa and features are purely illustrative; they don’t represent final judgments about what it would be worthwhile to investigate.) The database could either be used informally to guide and justify all-things-considered judgments, or it could be formalized into an algorithm that takes the table inputs and converts them into numerical estimates of comparative moral value across different animals. For the latter use, we ought also to conduct a sensitivity analysis and estimate our uncertainty for all the input parameters, so that we can identify where the value of new information is highest.
Such a project would be comparable in scope and structure to Rethink Priorities’ 2019 work on invertebrate sentience. Based on that analogy, I estimate that measuring capacity for welfare and moral status in this way would require somewhere between five thousand and seven thousand person-hours. In the rest of this section, I discuss some theoretical and practical obstacles that would need to be overcome in order to adequately measure capacity for welfare and moral status via the atomistic approach I have outlined. The list is certainly non-exhaustive, but it should give a representative flavor of the difficulties the atomistic approach faces. The obstacles are presented in increasing order of seriousness.
Choosing taxonomic rank
It is difficult to choose the right level of generality at which to try to measure capacity for welfare and moral status. There are competing considerations at play in this decision. On the one hand, there is pressure to drill down to a fairly narrow taxon (genus or species, say). The higher up the taxonomic hierarchy one goes, the more phylogenetically diverse a taxon becomes. If a taxon becomes too diverse, then the fact that a particular animal within the taxon possesses some relevant feature doesn’t guarantee that other animals within the taxon also possess the feature.
Recall from the first post in the series that, strictly speaking, capacity for welfare and moral status are properties of individuals. Obviously, it is not possible to investigate every individual animal that might be subject to some intervention in order to determine the individual animal’s capacity for welfare or moral status. As Kagan puts it: “After all, it would hardly be feasible to expect us to undertake a detailed investigation of a given animal’s specific psychological capacities each time we were going to interact with one. This makes it almost inevitable that in normal circumstances we will assign a given animal on the basis of its species (or, more likely still, on the basis of even larger, more general biological categories)” (Kagan 2019: 294). Moreover, we should expect that typical variation in capacity for welfare and moral status among members of the same species to be minimal. Generalizing to the level of species thus appears unproblematic.
Although generalizing to the level of species poses little theoretical difficulty, measuring capacity for welfare and moral status at that level is probably practically infeasible. There are hundreds of species that humans exploit in large numbers. Not only would it be difficult to investigate such a large number of animals, but the lower one goes in the taxonomic hierarchy, the less research is available that pertains to a given taxon. For all but the most commonly studied model organisms, it would be impossible to fill in the database at the level of species.
Moving a couple rungs up the taxonomic ladder to the rank of family improves the situation—but only slightly. There are approximately 50-60 families of animals that are directly exploited in large numbers. Moving up another rung in the ladder[30]—to the rank of order—reduces the number of taxa to be investigated to a more manageable 33.[31] (Some of those animals, such as jellyfish, bivalves, and nematodes, might be thought to lack moral standing and thus could possibly be safely ignored, further reducing the final number.) The difference between investigating moral status and capacity for welfare at the rank of order rather than family could be as high as a thousand person-hours.
Unfortunately, measuring capacity for welfare and moral status at the rank of order may gloss over important differences among animals. To give just one example: humans and lemurs are both in the order primates. However, many people find it implausible that humans and lemurs have the same moral status or capacity for welfare.[32] Thus, order may not be a fine-grained enough taxonomic rank to capture the relevant moral status facts.
Ultimately, the choice of taxonomic rank in the project must be guided by a balance of considerations. Move too low, and the project balloons in size and the probability of finding relevant scientific studies for each taxon plummets. Move too high, and important, action-relevant information will be missed. Personally, I think order is probably the right rank at which to investigate the subject. In part this belief is driven by the view that if moral status admits of degrees, then moral status is discrete and organized into a relatively small number of levels.[33] The smaller the number of tiers, the more sense it makes to investigate moral status at a higher taxonomic rank. It’s less plausible that capacity for welfare is discrete, so if one thinks capacity for welfare is much more important than moral status in determining characteristic moral worth, then one probably ought to favor a more fine-grained investigation.
Finding measurable proxies
The atomistic approach recommends first canvassing the philosophical literature to ascertain which general features determine capacity for welfare and moral status. Across plausible philosophical views, there appears to be a rough consensus as to what sorts of general features are relevant for moral status and capacity for welfare. Examples include: intensity of valenced experiences, self-awareness, general intelligence, autonomy, long-term planning, communicative ability, affective complexity, self-governance, abstract thought, creativity, sociability, and normative evaluation.[34] However, it’s one thing to identify general features that govern capacity for welfare and moral status. It’s another matter entirely to find empirically measurable proxies for those features. If these features cannot be operationalized in a way that allows them to be measured, then the atomistic approach cannot succeed.
The gravity of this concern depends of course on which features one believes determine moral status and capacity for welfare. Some features are more amenable to operationalization than others. If one believed, for instance, that neuron count wholly determines moral status and capacity for welfare, then one would have a relatively straightforward method for measuring moral worth.[35] Sadly, the view that neurons determine moral status or capacity for welfare appears rather unpromising. Neurons alone do not automatically generate conscious experience, and neurons are not themselves intrinsically morally valuable.[36] Larger animals need more neurons just to coordinate movement and autonomic functions. Larger animals also require more neurons to innervate their larger muscles,[37] and larger animals tend to process larger sensory fields to interact with their larger world, which requires a greater number of neurons just to process the data at the same level of complexity as a smaller animal would. Neuron counts alone do not tell us how the neurons are organized, how the neurons are used, or how many synaptic connections each neuron possesses. If neuron counts are worth investigating and comparing at all, it’s only because they are themselves rough proxies for characteristics we care about. Perhaps neuron count correlates roughly with affective sophistication or intensity of valenced experience or general intelligence.
Unfortunately, many of these potentially morally important characteristics seem extremely difficult to operationalize, despite repeated attempts to do so. For instance, a feature as amorphous as general intelligence is unlikely to be captured by any single metric. The biologists Lesley Rogers and Gisela Kaplan put the point this way: “Intelligence is not an entity that can be measured by performance on just one task, nor can it be inferred from brain size, as we discuss below. Here it is worth noting that pigeons, tested on a task based on one problem taken from a standard IQ test for humans, which required them to recognize symbols rotated at different angles, surpassed humans in performance of the same task (Delius, 1987). Would we therefore rank them above us in intelligence? Obviously, the single criterion of assessment is an inadequate measure for intelligence in a broad sense. Although IQ tests have some degree of limited validity in terms of predictability of academic success in a given culture and class in humans (Sternberg, Grigorenko, and Bundy, 2001), there is in fact no scientifically acceptable way of measuring intelligence as a broad set of characteristics in humans, let alone in animals. Add to this the ambition of making comparisons of intelligence across species and it is easy to see how flawed such attempts would have to be” (Rogers & Kaplan 2004: 177-178).
Although I am not quite so pessimistic as Rogers and Kaplan, it’s certainly worth acknowledging this difficulty at the outset of any attempt to measure general intelligence. Since many of the morally important features will be more akin to general intelligence than neuron count, we should expect the atomistic approach to allocate many hundreds of person-hours to the task of identifying measurable proxies for morally salient features. This task will almost certainly require the collaboration of experts across multiple domains.
Comparing features across animals
Even if measurable proxies for the features we care about could be found, we would still have to compare those proxies across animals. Since humans exploit such a large and phylogenetically diverse range of animals, comparing the features is not going to be easy. Experiments exploring rodent intelligence likely look very different from experiments exploring eel intelligence. Experiments exploring self-control in chickens likely look very different from experiments exploring self-control in octopuses. Experiments exploring cow emotions likely look very different from experiments exploring fruit fly emotions. Experiments exploring the sociability of sheep likely look very different from experiments exploring sociability in honey bees. And so on. To properly compare results across experiments on different types of animals, some sort of normalization across studies is required.
Fortunately, there already exists a scientific discipline that aims to compare difficult-to-measure features across different animals. Comparative cognition is an interdisciplinary field at the intersection of animal psychology, neurology, ethology, and evolutionary biology. Any attempt to measure capacity for welfare or moral status across animals will almost certainly rely heavily on comparative cognition studies. There are prominent comparative cognition labs across the globe. Examples include Cambridge’s Comparative Cognition Lab, University of Exeter’s Centre for Research in Animal Behaviour, Lund University’s Cognitive Zoology Group, Tufts University’s Comparative Cognition Lab, University of Helsinki’s Comparative Mind Group, Rochester Institute of Technology’s Comparative Cognition & Perception Lab, and IGDORE’s Interdisciplinary Research Group in Animal Behavioural Science.
In the last 15 years there has been a surge of interest in comparing species across a number of different interesting metrics. For example, MacLean et al. 2014 compare “the cognitive performance of 567 individuals representing 36 species on two problem-solving tasks measuring self-control” (E2140). In addition to direct comparisons, there are also a number of meta-analyses that compile data from multiple studies to arrive at comparative conclusions. For example, Cauchoix et al. 2018 “gathered 44 studies on individual performance of 25 species across six animal classes” in an effort to understand the evolution of cognition. Meanwhile, there has been a concomitant surge in theoretical discussions about how to compare features across species. For example Weiss et al. 2019 outline a quantitative measure of social complexity that works across species and Anderson & Andolphs 2014 develop a framework for studying emotions across species. These studies and others like them paint a promising picture of the potential of comparative cognition.
However, comparative cognition is a discipline still in its infancy. Because there may be a general bias toward non-null experimental results in the sciences, especially for relatively small and immature fields, we should be cautious about the conclusions of any one study (Ioannidis 2005). There is reason to think that academic journals favor papers with surprising results over papers which merely confirm the expected. Thus, there may be a publication bias in favor of animals doing surprising things. In the present case that might mean that comparative cognition studies which purport to demonstrate sophisticated cognitive abilities in nonhumans are overrepresented in the literature or that claims of comparability are exaggerated to gloss over undermining complications. Replication studies are, in general, under-rewarded in academia, so correcting for this overrepresentation and exaggeration may take years or even decades.
A recent (as yet unpublished) criticism of the field suggests comparative cognition research is biased because “(1) Phenomenon-based comparative cognition uses confirmatory research methods that are directionally biased, (2) In combination with a publication bias and a likely high rate of false discoveries, this bias suggests our literature contains many false positive findings, (3) This directional bias persists even with strong methodological criticism, and when researchers explicitly consider alternative explanations for the phenomena studied, (4) No formal method exists for generating and assessing theory-disconfirming evidence that could counter the biased positive evidence, (5) Ambiguity in definitions allow us as researchers to flexibly adjust our substantive claims depending on whether we are refuting criticism or selling the results, (6) The small size of comparative cognition as a research field perpetuates and reinforces points (1) - (5)” (Farrar & Ostojic 2019: 4). Together, these points favor a healthy skepticism when new research analogizes behavior across species or ascribes surprisingly sophisticated cognitive abilities to nonhuman animals.[38]
Some critics of comparative cognition worry that some questions the field pursues are premised on false assumptions. Daniel McShea complains of the “already fraught exercise of making comparisons across species lines,” wondering “how are we to compare the capabilities of, say, dusky titi monkeys with those of baboons? Dusky titis are smart about getting what they want, say, about the nuances of maintaining a pair bond. Baboons are also quite smart, but about different things, like navigating dominance hierarchies. Since the two species want such different things, since they are motivated to apply their non-affective capacities for such different purposes, one wonders whether it is even meaningful to ask which is smarter” (McShea 2017: 7). Yasushi Kiyokawa and Michael Hennessy worry that “the variety of approaches [...] precludes any strict standardization of procedures. These factors and even the backgrounds of the researchers themselves will continue to promote ambiguity and differences of opinion” (Kiyokawa & Hennessy 2018). Writing of comparisons of pain states in different animals, Edgar Walters and Amanda Williams have noted “the difficulty in defining pain in a way that allows pain [...] to be recognized and compared across species, a task that is especially challenging for attempted comparisons of the conscious component of pain,” observing that “there is considerable uncertainty about which behavioural features, neural circuits, cell types and molecules to compare across taxa” (Walters & Williams 2019: 6). In light of these difficulties, Lesley Rogers and Gisela Kaplan argue that “given our present state of knowledge of the needs and capabilities of classes of animals, let alone individual species, we feel, as biologists, that we first and foremost ought to guard against, or at least be very cautious about, the temptation of creating a scale of lesser or greater value of one species over another” (Rogers & Kaplan 2004: 196).
Even the best case looks unpromising. Suppose we adopted the view that neuron count is a good proxy for moral status and capacity for welfare. At first blush, that seems like a relatively easy feature to measure and compare. But, as it happens, neurons aren’t all created equal because not all areas of the brain are equally important. Brain regions that, say, merely innervate muscles are plausibly less important to moral status and capacity for welfare than brain regions that, say, govern emotional responses.[39] Thus, across species, the number of neurons in certain brain regions may be more informative than overall neuron count. Two animals with the same overall number of neurons might differ in morally salient ways if those neurons are distributed differently across brain regions. But even when comparing the same comparably-sized brain regions across species, various cytoarchitectural differences, such as the extent of cortical folding, interneuronal distance, axonal conduction velocity, degree of myelination, and synaptic transmission speed, could plausibly be more important still. To properly compare neurons, we need to know where they are located and how they are connected to each other. In many ways, the foregoing is an argument against taking neuron count to be a good proxy of moral status or capacity for welfare. But I hope it also serves to illustrate the general challenge of comparing even relatively simple physiological features, to say nothing of more complex, amorphous features such as general intelligence or affective sophistication.
All told, these worries suggest that comparing morally relevant features across phylogenetically distant animals will be fraught with theoretical and practical challenges. It will not always be clear which results are truly comparable, and as such, many difficult judgment calls will be required. It’s possible that these subjective judgment calls will be so numerous and so inescapable that any pretense of objectivity will be lost. In that case, the best method for improving our ability to measure capacity for welfare and moral status might be to fund more rigorous work at various comparative cognition labs so that better procedural standards for comparison can be developed.
Weighting the features
After canvassing the philosophical literature to find characteristics that contribute to moral status and capacity for welfare and canvassing the scientific literature to find measurable proxies for those characteristics, we will have a general list of features to investigate.[40] However, there is good cause to anticipate that not all of those features will be equally important. There are at least three reasons to think that the features will need to be weighted.
The first reason is that within a given theory of moral status or capacity for welfare, some features are more significant than others. This difference could be due to value pluralism. Objective list theories of welfare include among the list of intrinsic goods items such as happiness, virtue, wisdom, friendship, knowledge, and love. These items need not contribute to welfare equally. Even for a value monist view like hedonism, different features ought to be assigned different weights. There is no single proxy that perfectly captures capacity for pain and pleasure. A hedonist might think that self-awareness, linguistic sophistication, affective complexity, sociability, and long-term planning all influence the range and intensity of possible pleasures and pains a creature can experience. But it would be quite surprising if such diverse features contributed equally.
The second reason is that some features will be relevant to more theories than others, and in a relatively theory-neutral framework, the features ought to be weighted according to how many theories they are relevant to. Since the goal is to develop interventions that are robust in the face of our moral uncertainty, we should probably pay more attention to features that are salient across a spectrum of theories. For instance, although hedonism holds that pains and pleasures are the only things that matter for welfare, virtually all plausible theories of welfare hold that pains and pleasures are relevant to welfare, either directly or indirectly. Thus, perhaps, experiential features deserve more weight in the framework than, say, agential features[41] that may be relevant to fewer theories.
For simplicity I’m here assuming perfect theory-neutrality among a small number of theories. In reality, although we might want to consider multiple theories, we might lean toward some theories more than others. In that case, each feature would need to be weighted not only by the number of theories to which the feature is relevant but also by the plausibility of the theories to which the theory is relevant. And even if a feature is relevant to multiple theories, it may not be equally important to each theory. So the features would need to be weighted not only according to how many theories to which they are relevant, but also by how important they are to the theories for which they are relevant.
The final reason is that we may want to operationalize characteristics in more than one way. For instance, we may want to include a collection of physiological features[42] in the database. Physiological features plausibly aren’t intrinsically valuable; they’re merely proxies for other categories. Suppose, for instance, we thought general intelligence (whatever that means exactly) is pretty important for moral status or capacity for welfare. We might want to estimate general intelligence through a combination of neurological features (e.g., encephalization quotient, cortical neuron count) and behavioral features (e.g., tool use, uncertainty monitoring). Since no proxy will be perfect and it will be unclear which proxy is best, we will probably want to operationalize most characteristics in multiple ways. This needs to be reflected in the weighting system. If some characteristics are operationalized in more ways than others, then weighting features equally would amount to double-counting some characteristics.
Weighting the features looks important and inevitable. But doing so will be incredibly tough. Jean Kazez explains the difficulty thusly: “There are many capacities to which we assign positive value, but we don’t always have a definite idea of their relative values. If we’re trying to rank bower birds, crows, and wolves, it depends what’s more valuable, artistic ability (which favors the bower bird) or sheer intelligence (which favors the crow) or sociability (which favors the wolf). We’re not going to be able to put these three species on separate rungs of a ladder, in any particular order, and neither is the situation quite as crisp as a straightforward tie. We just don’t know how to assign them a place on the ladder, relative to each other” (Kazez 2010: 87-88).
The trouble gets even worse when we consider so-called combination effects: “A property might raise the moral status of one being but not another, because it might raise moral status only when combined with certain other properties” (Harman 2003: 177-178). For example, it might be the case that a certain degree of autonomy is required before some prosocial capacities contribute to moral status. Maybe nurturing behavior that is entirely pre-programmed and instinctive counts for less than love freely given. Honey bees and cows both care for their young, but if we think cows have a greater capacity for rational choice than honey bees, then the same level of juvenile guardianship might raise the moral status of cows more than honey bees.[43] Thus, the feature weights may not be static or independent. Instead, they might be dynamic and interdependent. That is, the weight of a given feature may depend on the presence or absence of other features. Accounting for this complexity appears staggeringly hard.
In sum, accurate point estimates of the relative weights of the features are probably unachievable. The intellectually honest thing to do is to assign each feature a range of weights.[44] But these ranges might be so wide as to rob the project of any action-guiding conclusions. That is, one’s views about the comparative moral value of different animals might depend almost wholly on how one interprets the relative importance of different features. If there’s nothing to be done to justifiably narrow the range of plausible weights, then the project may well end up countenancing a huge range of tradeoffs among species. If the project doesn’t tell us anything practical about which tradeoffs are permissible, then it is almost useless.
Conclusion
One cannot work in effective animal advocacy and wholly ignore the question of comparative moral value. Resources are finite, so tradeoffs among different animals are inevitable. Every time an organization launches a campaign, a researcher investigates a question, or a grantmaker funds a project, tradeoffs are made. The time, money, and attention that are devoted to one species could also have been devoted to another.
Although practical concerns will always guide our decision-making to some extent, it’s important to think about how we would ideally like to distribute resources. If the ideal distribution of resources differs significantly from what is currently feasible, we ought to devote time and money to surmounting those obstacles. It is not an immutable fact that, say, fish elicit little sympathy from the general public or that fish welfare organizations are few in number. If fish welfare is neglected relative to its importance, we can use our resources to improve tractability and overcome limiting factors.
To understand the ideal distribution of resources, we must understand the comparative value of different types of animals. If animal experiences and interests are all equal, then we should aim for interventions that have the greatest impact for the greatest number. Such a view would almost certainly push us to care more for small, numerous invertebrates than we currently do.
However, if some animals lack moral standing, then we should exclude those animals from our moral consideration. If that’s the case, it’s important to know where to draw the line between animals that have moral standing and those that do not. It’s also important to know the consequences of drawing the line in one place rather than another, how confident we are in drawing the line, and what information would cause us to change where we draw the line.
If some animals have moral standing and others lack it, then by definition animals differ in their moral status and capacity for welfare. But there are plausible reasons to think that among the animals that have moral standing, there will be further variation in moral status or capacity for welfare. If that’s the case, then saving the lives of one type of animal will not always have the same intrinsic moral value as saving the lives of other types of animals.[45] The suffering of, say, chimpanzees and octopuses may count for more, morally, than the suffering of, say, mealworms and prawn.
To determine the ideal allocation of resources, we need some way to measure capacity for welfare and moral status. Doing so will not be easy. The philosophical terrain is treacherous. Our intuitions are imprecise and likely skewed. The scientific literature is vast but uncertain. Still, even a small reduction in our uncertainty could make a big difference to our allocative decision-making. There are many years ahead to refine such estimates. But we can’t put off making tradeoffs now.
Credits
This essay is a project of Rethink Priorities. It was written by Jason Schukraft. Thanks to Kim Cuddington, Marcus A. Davis, Neil Dullaghan, David Moss, and Jeff Sebo for helpful feedback. If you like our work, please consider subscribing to our newsletter. You can see all our work to date here.
Works Cited
Anderson, D. J., & Adolphs, R. (2014). A framework for studying emotions across species. Cell, 157(1), 187-200.
Bradley, A., Mennie, N., Bibby, P. A., & Cassaday, H. J. (2020). Some animals are more equal than others: Validation of a new scale to measure how attitudes to animals depend on species and human purpose of use. PloS one, 15(1), e0227948.
Browning, H. (2020). Assessing Measures of Animal Welfare. PhilSci Archive, accessed May 2020.
Birch, J. (2017). Animal sentience and the precautionary principle. Animal Sentience: An Interdisciplinary Journal on Animal Feeling, 2(16), 1.
Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2014). Gender and philosophical intuition. Experimental Philosophy Volume 2, 307-346. Oxford University Press.
Budolfson, M., & Spears, D. (2019). Quantifying Animal Well-Being and Overcoming the Challenge of Interspecies Comparisons. in B. Fischer (ed) The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics (pp. 92-101). Routledge.
Cauchoix, M., Chow, P. K. Y., Van Horik, J. O., Atance, C. M., Barbeau, E. J., Barragan-Jason, G., … & Cauchard, L. (2018). The repeatability of cognitive performance: a meta-analysis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 373(1756), 20170281.
Costa, A., Foucart, A., Hayakawa, S., Aparici, M., Apesteguia, J., Heafner, J., & Keysar, B. (2014). Your morals depend on language. PloS one, 9(4), e94842.
Cuddington, K., Fortin, M. J., Gerber, L. R., Hastings, A., Liebhold, A., O’connor, M., & Ray, C. (2013). Process‐based models are required to manage ecological systems in a changing world. Ecosphere, 4(2), 1-12.
De Cruz, H. (2015). Where philosophical intuitions come from. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(2), 233-249.
Dicke, U., & Roth, G. (2016). Neuronal factors determining high intelligence. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 371(1685), 20150180.
Farrar, B. G., & Ostojic, L. (2019). The illusion of science in comparative cognition. PsyArXiv. October 2, 2019.
Harman, E. (2003). The potentiality problem. Philosophical Studies, 114(1), 173-198.
Herzog, H. (2010). The Importance of Being Cute. in Some We Love, Some We Hate, Some We Eat, Harper Collins, 37-66.
Herzog, H., Grayson, S., & McCord, D. (2015). Brief measures of the animal attitude scale. Anthrozoös, 28(1), 145-152.
Ioannidis, J. P. (2005). Why most published research findings are false. PLos med, 2(8), e124.
Jardim-Messeder, D., Lambert, K., Noctor, S., Pestana, F. M., de Castro Leal, M. E., Bertelsen, M. F., … & Herculano-Houzel, S. (2017). Dogs have the most neurons, though not the largest brain: trade-off between body mass and number of neurons in the cerebral cortex of large carnivoran species. Frontiers in Neuroanatomy, 11, 118.
Kagan, S. (2019). How to count animals, more or less. Oxford University Press.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Macmillan.
Kazez, J. (2010). Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals. Wiley-Blackwell.
Kiyokawa, Y., & Hennessy, M. B. (2018). Comparative studies of social buffering: A consideration of approaches, terminology, and pitfalls. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 86, 131-141.
Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92(3), B1-B12.
MacLean, E. L., Hare, B., Nunn, C. L., Addessi, E., Amici, F., Anderson, R. C., … & Boogert, N. J. (2014). The evolution of self-control. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111(20), E2140-E2148.
McShea, D. W. (2017). Logic, passion and the problem of convergence. Interface Focus, 7(3), 20160122.
Miralles, A., Raymond, M., & Lecointre, G. (2019). Empathy and compassion toward other species decrease with evolutionary divergence time. Scientific Reports, 9(1), 1-8.
Norwood, F. B., & Lusk, J. L. (2011). Compassion, by the pound: the economics of farm animal welfare. Oxford University Press.
Rogers, L., & Kaplan, G. (2004). All animals are not equal: the interface between scientific knowledge and legislation for animal rights. in C. R. Sunstein and M. Nussbaum (eds) Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 175-202.
Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non‐philosophers. Mind & Language, 27(2), 135-153.
Sebo, J. (2020). How to Count Animals, more or less, by Shelly Kagan. Mind.
Serpell, J. A. (2004). Factors influencing human attitudes to animals and their welfare. Animal Welfare 13, S145-S152.
Singer, P. (2011). Practical ethics, 3rd Edition. Cambridge University Press.
Swain, S., Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. M. (2008). The instability of philosophical intuitions: Running hot and cold on truetemp. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 138-155.
Walters, E. T., & Williams, A. C. D. C. (2019). Evolution of mechanisms and behaviour important for pain. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 20190275.
Weathers, S. T., Caviola, L., Scherer, L., Pfister, S., Fischer, B., Bump, J. B., & Jaacks, L. M. (2020). Quantifying the Valuation of Animal Welfare Among Americans. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 1-22.
Weiss, M. N., Franks, D. W., Croft, D. P., & Whitehead, H. (2019). Measuring the complexity of social associations using mixture models. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 73(1), 8.
Wuensch, K. L., Jenkins, K. W., & Poteat, G. M. (2002). Misanthropy, idealism and attitudes towards animals. Anthrozoös, 15(2), 139-149.
Wynne, C. D. L. (2007). What are Animals? Why Anthropomorphism is Still Not a Scientific Approach to Behavior. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 2, 125-135.
Notes
- ↩︎
This is very much not an exhaustive list.
- ↩︎
See this spreadsheet for details. By my count, every order in the spreadsheet is exploited in numbers greater than ~50 million individuals per year.
- ↩︎
Humans also indirectly affect many wild animals, and many wild animals suffer independent of any human interference. In this series I focus primarily on animals that humans exploit directly, most of which are farmed. Because the goal of the project is to improve the way resources are allocated across interventions, it makes sense at this time to focus on animals that are directly exploited. As the effective animal advocacy movement identifies more interventions to aid wild animals, we will want to include those animals in our measures of comparative moral value.
- ↩︎
See Budolfson & Spears 2019 for more on the measurement problem.
- ↩︎
A method that was more limited (to say farmed land vertebrates) could still be useful even if less than ideal.
- ↩︎
This list is adapted from Browning 2020. Her focus is on measuring realized welfare, but I think the desiderata apply equally well to measuring capacity for welfare and moral status.
- ↩︎
I’m not claiming here that philosophical disputes are in principle irresolvable, just that they are usually much less tractable than empirical questions.
- ↩︎
For instance, we may want to adopt a precautionary principle (Birch 2017) in the face of large uncertainty.
- ↩︎
For a recent example to the contrary, see Founders Pledge’s report comparing the value of donations to The Humane League to the value of donations to the Against Malaria Foundation. For another potential example to the contrary, see Charity Entrepreneurship’s weighted welfare index. Note that although the CE index is meant to improve the way resources are allocated across species, it does not explicitly address moral status or capacity for welfare.
- ↩︎
He adds, “Some comparisons may be too difficult. We may have to say that we have not the slightest idea whether it would be better to be a fish or a snake; but then, we do not very often find ourselves forced to choose between killing a fish or a snake. Other comparisons might not be so difficult. In general, it does seem that the more highly developed the mental life of the being, the greater the degree of self-awareness and rationality and the broader the range of possible experiences, the more one would prefer that kind of life, if one were choosing between it and a being at a lower level of awareness” (Singer 2011: 92).
- ↩︎
Note that Kagan’s presentation is a bit misleading here. Comparing the welfare of a human’s lifetime with the welfare of a fly’s lifetime is a comparison in diachronic welfare, that is, welfare over time. But humans live much longer than flies; thus they have much longer to amass welfare. So it’s not really a fair comparison. Fruit flies only live about 30 days. If one refused to forgo a single day of human life for an extra lifetime (30 days) as a fly, we should infer that a day in the life of a typical fly contains less than one thirtieth the welfare of a day in the life of a typical human.
- ↩︎
- ↩︎
See Herzog, Grayson, & McCord 2015 for a shorter version of the scale.
- ↩︎
Mice, rats, rabbits, pigs, monkeys, octopuses, chickens, badgers, zebrafish, tree shrews, dogs, dolphins, parrots, chimpanzees, badgers, and pigeons.
- ↩︎
The specific uses are medical research, basic science research, food production, pest control, and “other.” Note that specifying specific uses probably introduces many confounding influences to the responses.
- ↩︎
The survey was conducted for the American Farm Bureau Federation and is unfortunately no longer available online. Norwood and Lusk discuss the survey in their 2011 book Compassion, by the Pound: The Economics of Farm Animal Welfare (pp. 171-172). A popularization of the survey appeared in Reason magazine under the title “You=11,500 Sheep.”
- ↩︎
The survey utilized a multiple-choice format, so respondents were not able to input any number they wanted for X. For all questions, the first program affected one thousand animals and the possible values for X for the second program were 1, 500, 1001, 2000, 5000, 10000, 100000, and 1000000.
- ↩︎
Also of note: “Nearly one-third (30%) of respondents reported that they believed animal suffering should be taken into account to a degree equal to or above human suffering” (1).
- ↩︎
As just one example of the extent of this ignorance, I hypothesize that few members of the general public would guess that snails are more closely related to squid than earthworms are to silkworms.
- ↩︎
It may still be useful to survey the lay public. Such surveys may help us identify biases that influence ours and others’ judgments. It’s also possible that a wide enough survey may reveal a latent ‘wisdom of the crowd,’ which would allow us to extract a useful signal from the random noise of our unreliable, arbitrary intuitions.
- ↩︎
See Cuddington et al. 2013 for more on the tradeoff between the speed and opacity of expert judgment: “While the development of a rule may take some time, expert opinion can be accessed rapidly in most cases, and in some cases is the only information available (O’Neill et al. 2008). However, the role of theory and the assumptions behind expert opinion and rules of thumb are rarely transparent, so there may be little potential for evaluating the assumptions that support models of this sort. Expert opinions inevitably are divergent (e.g., Czembor et al. 2011), although there may be techniques for building consensus among a group of experts (e.g., Delphi technique, Rowe and Wright 1999). It is also possible that the rules of thumb or expert opinion do not include adequate concepts of scale and uncertainty (e.g., Burgman 2005) that are a requirement for appropriate management under global change. However, when the main requirement is that a decision be made extremely quickly with very limited data, expert opinion or rule‐based models have a clear time advantage over other types of models” (3).
- ↩︎
For an overview of the biases and heuristics literature, see Kahneman 2011. For philosophical examples, see, among others, Machery et al. 2004; Swain, Alexander, & Weinberg 2008; Buckwalter & Stich 2014; and Costa et al. 2014. See Schwitzgebel & Cushman 2012 for a series of experiments in which the moral judgments of professional philosophers were as sensitive to order effects as the judgments of non-philosophers. See De Cruz 2015 §6 for a general discussion about whether these findings undermine the view that professional philosophers are ‘expert intuiters.’
- ↩︎
See Serpell 2004, Wynne 2007, and Herzog 2010 for overviews.
- ↩︎
Alternatively, the exercise might tell us something about average realized welfare rather than capacity for welfare. A species might have a huge capacity for welfare, but if in fact the members of that species tend to lead net-negative lives, we would never want to be a member of that species.
- ↩︎
Similar concerns apply to measuring the relative value of human health outcomes, which is crucial for calculating QALYs.
- ↩︎
Of course, which facts are available in the scientific literature might be influenced by bias. There is probably comparatively more information on traits that humans find interesting.
- ↩︎
In many respects, the first post in this series already plays this role. However, that post does not explicitly weight the features relevant for moral status or capacity for welfare.
- ↩︎
This stage might benefit from a survey of relevant philosophical experts.
- ↩︎
The cells are empty not only because the relevant scientific literature has not been surveyed but also because it is as yet unclear what sort of response the cells merit. Ideally, we want the cells to be comparable, even when the cells are reporting very different metrics, so it might make most sense to score each cell on some arbitrary scale (e.g., from 1 to 10). But standardizing the process looks really difficult. See the objections section for more discussion.
- ↩︎
Ignoring superfamilies, infraorders, and suborders, which not all orders have
- ↩︎
See this spreadsheet for an overview.
- ↩︎
One might think humans are unique and thus that this is a special case that says little about the general point. So here is a non-human example: among species in the Carnivora order, neuron count differs by a factor of 24 and brain mass differs by a factor of at least 58 (Jardim-Messeder et al. 2017).
- ↩︎
Kagan believes there are only around six tiers of moral status (2019: 293).
- ↩︎
See the first post in the series for details.
- ↩︎
In practice, measuring neuron counts is actually anything but straightforward. See the work of Suzana Herculano-Houzel for many discussions of the various complications.
- ↩︎
We can imagine a lump of billions of neurons swirling around a laboratory jar with no capacity for welfare or moral standing. Conversely, we can imagine an alien or a computer program with zero neurons which nonetheless has a high moral status and capacity for welfare.
- ↩︎
This does not necessarily give them greater precision in movement; insects on average have similar numbers of distinct muscles in total.
- ↩︎
On the other hand, there appears to be a longstanding and preexisting speciesist prejudice against attributing complex mental states to nonhuman animals. Given such a prejudice, scientists and the lay public may have been systematically underestimating the cognitive abilities of nonhuman animals for a long time. Today’s “surprising” results might just be the product of science finally beginning to overcome deep-rooted prejudice. And insofar as the prejudice persists, the competing forces of positive publication bias and speciesist prejudice might even approximately cancel each other out, leaving us with a literature that is largely reliable (though this is an unlikely outcome). In any event, the results captured in the comparative moral value database ought to be checked and updated on a continual basis. If there is a particular study that carries outsized weight in the final analysis, it may be worthwhile to fund a lab to replicate the study.
- ↩︎
See Dicke & Roth 2016 for more on the importance of cortical neurons, neuron packing density, interneuronal distance and axonal conduction velocity.
- ↩︎
I tentatively estimate we’ll end up with about 30 features on the list.
- ↩︎
Examples of agential features include self-awareness, self-control, number of behavior types, executive functions, long-term planning, and capacity for moral responsibility.
- ↩︎
Examples of physiological features include neuron count, presence of nociceptors, connection of nociceptors to central nervous system, and presence of endogenous opioids.
- ↩︎
In a recent talk at Notre Dame, Eric Schwitzgebel offers the example of “a superpleasure machine but one with little or no capacity for rational thought. It’s like one giant, irrational orgasm all day long. Would it be great to make such things and terrible to destroy them, or is such irrational pleasure not really something worth much in the moral calculus?” Schwitzgebel is here wondering whether degree of rationality affects the moral value of capacity for pleasure, which would be another example of a combination effect.
- ↩︎
It would also be helpful to assign probability distributions to the question ‘What weight would you assign to the feature after one hundred more hours of research?’ See this comment from NunoSempere about doing so in the context of investigating sentience.
- ↩︎
Obviously, when comparing lives saved across species, differences in lifespan will need to be accounted for.
- An Introduction to the Moral Weight Project by 31 Oct 2022 9:13 UTC; 179 points) (
- Rethink Priorities 2020 Impact and 2021 Strategy by 25 Nov 2020 13:28 UTC; 118 points) (
- The Subjective Experience of Time: Welfare Implications by 27 Jul 2020 13:24 UTC; 113 points) (
- Prioritising animal welfare over global health and development? by 13 May 2023 9:03 UTC; 112 points) (
- Comparisons of Capacity for Welfare and Moral Status Across Species by 18 May 2020 0:42 UTC; 101 points) (
- “Disappointing Futures” Might Be As Important As Existential Risks by 3 Sep 2020 1:15 UTC; 96 points) (
- Differences in the Intensity of Valenced Experience across Species by 30 Oct 2020 1:13 UTC; 93 points) (
- Does Critical Flicker-Fusion Frequency Track the Subjective Experience of Time? by 3 Aug 2020 13:30 UTC; 68 points) (
- Perceived Moral Value of Animals and Cortical Neuron Count by 25 Aug 2023 14:52 UTC; 53 points) (
- EA Organization Updates: May 2020 by 22 Jun 2020 10:44 UTC; 31 points) (
- 20 Feb 2023 21:51 UTC; 28 points) 's comment on Rethink Priorities’ Welfare Range Estimates by (
- Why might one value animals far less than humans? by 8 Jun 2020 1:54 UTC; 27 points) (
- 25 Sep 2020 14:15 UTC; 25 points) 's comment on Thomas Kwa’s Quick takes by (
- 30 Sep 2020 16:09 UTC; 18 points) 's comment on Ramiro’s Quick takes by (
- What was the first being on Earth to experience suffering? by 10 Jul 2020 8:05 UTC; 14 points) (
- How to assign numerical values to individual welfare? by 29 Jul 2021 13:52 UTC; 2 points) (
Great post, and I’m excited to see RP work on this. I have great confidence in your carefulness about this.
A concern I have with pretty much every approach to weighting welfare across species is that it seems like the correct weights may depend on the type of experience. For example, I could imagine the intensity of physical pain being very similar across species but the severity of depression from not being able to move to vary greatly.
Is there a way to allow for this within the approach you lay out here?
Hi Zach,
Thanks for your comment. Measuring and comparing welfare across species is a tremendous theoretical and practical challenge. For measuring capacity for welfare, we would want to get a rough sense of the range of physical pain and pleasure an animal can experience as well as the range of emotional pain and pleasure an animal can experience. We would also want to know the degree to which physical and emotional pain/pleasure contribute to overall welfare, and this may differ by species. (We will need to account for combination effects: among other things, “stacking” one unit of physical pain on top of one unit of emotional pain may create more or less than two units of overall suffering.) All else being equal, if two animals have the same range of possible physical pains and pleasures, but animal A has a greater range of possible emotional pains and pleasures than animal B, we would expect animal A to have a greater capacity for welfare than animal B.
One thing to keep in mind is that what ultimately matters morally is realized welfare, not capacity for welfare. In many instances, judging the effectiveness of an intervention will require looking at species-specific differences in the way welfare is realized. Two animals may have the same overall capacity for welfare, and they may be subject to the same conditions (solitary confinement, say), but species-specific differences (one is a social animal and the other is not, say) may indicate that one animal suffers much more than the other in those conditions.
Nonetheless, I do believe thinking about capacity for welfare will help increase the efficiency with which our resources are allocated across interventions, especially when applied to big-picture questions, like “What percentage of our resources should ideally go to fish or crustaceans or insects?”
I hope I’m not being too obvious here, but I’ve seen people frequently speak of animals “mattering” X times as much as a human, say, without drawing this distinction: we’d need to be very careful to distinguish what we mean by value of life. For prioritizing which lives to save, this quote perhaps makes sense. But not if “value of animal lives” is meant to correspond to how much we should prioritize alleviating different animals’ suffering. I wouldn’t trade days of my life to experience days of a very poor person’s life, but that doesn’t mean my life is more valuable in the sense that helping me is more important. Quite the opposite: the less value there is in a human’s/animal’s life, the more imperative it is to help them (in non-life-saving ways), for reasons of diminishing returns at least.
I would strongly encourage surveys about intuitions of this sort to precisely ask about tradeoffs of experiences, rather than “value of life” (as in the Norwood and Lusk survey that you cite).
Yeah, I agree that estimating welfare (either average realized welfare or capacity for welfare) this way is a bad strategy for a number of reasons. There are going to be many confounders and the framing of the thought experiment obscures rather than clarifies the issue.
Combination effects seem challenging as you point out. I think it’s often taken for granted that weighting things should be done linearly, but there really isn’t any reason to believe this would approximate the moral truth or what we’d want to care about upon reflection in this domain, although it’s useful for its simplicity, interpretability and transparency.
Another specific challenge is whether we should apply a given (usually monotonic) transformation to a feature that comes in degrees first. For example, if the degree of X matters, say neuron count or neuron count in a particular part of the brain, should we use X,X2,√X,logX,2X or something else? There are infinitely many degrees of freedom here.
Hi Jason, thank you for writing this. I appreciate the refreshing reiteration that we do and must make trade-offs between the interests of different species, as well as your careful philosophical treatment. A few thoughts:
While capacity and moral weight are important parameters, I think there also remains significant empirical uncertainty about actual experience as well. Without eliminating this uncertainty, estimate of the two former values may not be especially useful.
As you indicate, these are, of course, not mutually exclusive. However, I suspect they overlap so much as to be not worth distinguishing as any reasonable application would apply both approaches. As you suggest, the weightings of the atomistic features would rely on expert judgement, as would estimates of combination effects, which could occur at the species (or even individual) level. For example, Bracke 2019 is the best study I’ve seen on comparing a wide array of chicken housing condition. In the study, a panel of chicken welfare experts were provided a set of “atomistic” attributes (eg, stocking density, temperature, light exposure) about different housing conditions to inform holistic judgments of the relative welfare of each system. While this is not exactly the same task as assessing capacity for welfare and moral status, it seems analogous and illustrative of the need for a hybrid approach.
I agree, but this might be mitigated by including these as explanatory variables. For example, the impact of speciesism could at least be examined and potentially controlled for by inclusion of the above-cited speciesism scale or the impact of diet patterns by inclusion of a diet screener.
This seems very unlikely to be the correct taxa in my opinion. First, taxa above genus or family are generally arbitrary in scope. Second, relevant traits would likely be heterogeneous within such a broad group. For example, within the order of bivalves, there are sessile and motile species, and species with a dozen plus compound eyes or “eyes” that detect only light and dark.
Hi Jacob,
Thanks for your comment! I’m happy to chat in more detail if you’d like to set up a call.
I agree, and I fully support more research aimed at figuring out how to measure realized welfare. For many comparisons of specific interventions, learning more about the realized welfare of a given group of animals (and how a change in conditions would affect realized welfare) is going to be much more action-relevant than information about capacity for welfare. Considerations pertaining to capacity for welfare are most pertinent to big-picture questions about how we should allocate resources across fairly distinct types of animals (e.g., chickens vs. fish vs. crustaceans vs. insects). I think some uncertainties surrounding capacity for welfare can be resolved without fully solving the problem of how to measure realized welfare in every case. Of course, measuring realized welfare and measuring capacity for welfare share many of the same conceptual and practical hurdles, so we may be able to make progress on the two in tandem.
Not sure how much we disagree here. I certainly think all-things-considered expert judgments have an important role to play in assessing capacity for welfare. The post emphasizes the atomistic approach because it’s a lot more complicated (and thus warrants deeper explanation) and also because it’s much more likely to uncover action-relevant information that our untutored all-things-considered judgments may miss. (I liken the project to RP’s previous work on invertebrate sentience, which required many subjective judgment calls but ultimately whose main contribution was a compilation of hard data on 53 empirically measurable features that are relevant to assessing whether or not an animal is sentient.)
Yeah, I could be convinced that order is the wrong taxonomic rank. My main concern is tractability. The scale of the potential project is already so enormous, and moving from order to family could easily add another 500-1000 hours of work. My hope was that we would be able to discern some broad trends at the level of order (which could be refined in the future). But if neither time nor money were a particular concern, then, for the reasons you outline, I think family would be a much better rank at which to investigate these questions.
Again, happy to talk more if you’re interested!
Thanks for the helpful clarifications and responses, Jason. I don’t have anything to add at this point, but look forward to reading more of your work!
Thanks for writing this up. It seems what you’ve done with the atomistic approach is stated what, in principle, one would need to do, but not really wrestled with the difficulties and details of doing it. By analogy, it’s a bit like you’ve said “if we want to get to space, we need to build a spaceship” and but not said how to build a spaceship (“well, it would need to get into space, and carry people, …”)
I think it would help to spell out a particular issue. Suppose we think happiness, the intrinsic pleasurableness/displeasurableness of experiences is one of the things that constitutes welfare. Okay, what proxy do we use for that? Happiness is a subjective experience, so no objective measure is possible. Of course, we have intuitions about relative magnitudes of happiness in different animals, but what makes us think we’re right, even approximately?
(I note I raised effectively the same concern in your previous post and you haven’t (yet) replied to my latest comment. You linked me this paper, but it doesn’t address my concern: the author surveys didn’t “suffering calculators” but doesn’t provide an account of how we would test that some are more valid that others).
Hi Michael,
Thanks for your comment.
This is an important concern, but I think we disagree about what it would take to satisfy this concern. It’s true that we don’t and can’t have direct access to the subjective experience of nonhuman animals. But of course we also don’t and can’t have direct access to the subjective experience of other humans. Subjective experience is, well, subjective. So whenever we conclude that a fellow human is happy or sad, we’re doing so on the basis of indirect evidence.
Now, most humans can give verbal reports of their subjective states, which is about as good a kind of indirect evidence as we could hope for. But not all humans can do that. I take it as a datum that we can know a great deal about the subjective states of babies. Maybe you deny that. If so, that’s an interesting crux.
If you agree that we can know about the subjective states of babies, then that establishes that it is in principle possible to know about the subjective experience of non-verbal animals in the absence of direct evidence. Admittedly, this type of inference gets harder as we move to nonhuman animals, and harder still as we move farther out in phylogenetic distance. But we should clearly distinguish practical difficulties from conceptual difficulties. There’s nothing particularly conceptually dubious about abductive reasoning; inference to the best explanation is used in many areas of both philosophy and science.
Have you read Michael Tye’s Tense Bees and Shell-Shocked Crabs? He discusses these questions in a bit more detail. You could also take a look at our introduction to the invertebrate sentience project, especially the project rationale section. I’d be happy to schedule a meeting to talk in more detail if you want.
Thanks for your response, but I don’t think you’re grasping the nettle of my objection. I agree with you that you and I both think we know something about the mental states of other adult humans and, further, human babies. I also think such assumptions are reasonable, if empirically unprovable. But that’s not my point.
In short, my challenge is: articulate and defend the method you will use to determine how much more or less happy humans are than non-humans animals in particular contexts—say the average humans vs the average factory farmed chicken.
Here’s what I think we can do with humans. We assume you and I have the same capacity for happiness. We assume we are able to learn about the experiences of others and communicate them via language, e.g. we’ve both stubbed our toes, but I haven’t broken my leg, and when you say “breaking my leg is 10x worse” I can conclude that would be true for me too. Hence, when you say “I feel 2/10″ or “I feel terrible” I might feel confident you mean the same things by those as I do.
What can do with chickens? We really have no idea what chickens’ capacities for happiness are—is it 1/10th, 1/100th, etc? It doesn’t seem at all reasonable to assume they are roughly the same as ours. The chicken cannot tell us how happy how it is relative to its maximum, our maximum, or, indeed, tell us anything at all. Of course, we may have intuitions—what we might perjoratively call “tummy feelings”—about these things. Fine. But what method do we use to assess if those intuitions are correct? The application of further intuitive reflection? Surely not. I cannot think of a justifiable empirical method to inform our priors. If you can explain why this project is not doomed, I would love to know why! But I fear it is.
Hi Michael,
Thanks for your comment. This is a complicated topic, so it’s easy for well-meaning folks to talk past one another. For that reason, I’ll encourage you again to reach out to schedule a call to discuss in further detail.
Since this area is so under-explored, I think there is a large range of reasonable expectations about the outcome of the sort of project I outline in the post. I can try to give you some insight into why I’m more optimistic than you are, but that’s not to say that your pessimism is outside the range of reasonable attitudes one could take to the project.
One reason I’m optimistic is because in my own limited experience exploring questions of comparative moral value, the returns have thus far been quite high. Let me give just one example.
The subjective experience of time is plausibly an important determinant of realized welfare and capacity for welfare. There are plausible empirical proxies we can use to approximate differences in the subjective experience of time. Critical flicker-fusion frequency (CFF) is an especially well-studied measure, so I’ll use it in this example, but I think there are probably better metrics. (I’m currently writing a report on this subject; stay tuned for details.) If CFF tracks the subjective experience of time, then higher values represent more subjective moments per objective unit of time. The typical human has a max CFF threshold of around 60 Hz. Chickens have a max CFF threshold around 87 Hz. Honey bees have a max CFF threshold of around 200 Hz. So that’s an example of a way we might directly compare three important animals on a metric that might track an important welfare determinant.
Now I’m not saying CFF is a perfect measure of the subjective experience of time. It’s not. In fact, my best guess is that there’s only a ~30% chance it tracks the subjective experience of time under the best conditions. (Again, see my forthcoming report for extensive discussion.) But the illustrative point here is that there may exist empirically measurable proxies for features we care about that allow us to compare capacity for welfare across species. If we don’t at least try to locate such proxies, we’ll never know if they exist. Given the stakes, it seems reasonable to me to devote a small fraction of our collective resources to think more carefully about these very difficult issues.
I share your overall pessimism of arriving at an answer that will actually be satisfying philosophically, but I do think research in this area is still important and useful. Our ultimately subjective judgements can be better informed.
I think the same problem applies here too, because of the uniqueness of humans (our nervous systems, the density of nerve endings, the thickness of our skin, etc.), although it’s much more reasonable to generalize from one human to another than between species, because of similarity. Still, I don’t think it’s actually reasonable, using the same standard; I might as well be a talking alien. And we have no way of objectively quantifying how reasonable this approximation is or whether one human’s welfare capacity is greater or lower than another’s.
That being said, I don’t think you always need this assumption for humans anyway, e.g. if you’re randomly sampling humans to survey from the same distribution that you’re generalizing to (or sampling humans to generalize to), since the estimator can be chosen to be statistically unbiased, regardless of how well it measures what we actually care about. (However, in practice, the distributions often aren’t the same, and we know of generalizability issues due to that, e.g. WEIRD. You can adjust/match/control for certain characteristics, but you can never really eliminate all bias. And for something subjective like welfare, we can’t bound the bias from the underlying concept we care aout, either, even if it were possible to bound the statistical bias, for the same reason we can’t bound how different my experience of a toe stub is from yours.)
On the other hand, we can’t do this with nonhuman animals, since we’re sampling from humans and generalizing beyond humans. The distributions are definitely not the same.
Right. My thought is that we assume humans have the same capacity on average, because while there might be differences, we don’t know which way they’ll go so they should ‘wash out’ as statistical noise. Pertinently, this same response doesn’t work for animals because we really don’t know what their relatively max capacities are.
FWIW, the analogue to my response here would be to say we can expect all chickens to have approximately the same capacity as each other, even if individuals chickens differ. The claim isn’t about humans per se, but about similarities borne out of genetics.
In another comment, I mentioned that I think this is actually only fair to assume while we don’t know much about the individual humans. We could break this symmetry pretty easily.
Since humans also differ from each other genetically, isn’t the distinction here just a matter of degree?
You might also think you can generalize between you and I using a symmetry argument, but this is only by willful ignorance. We could learn more about each other in a way that would suggest one of us experiences certain things more intensely than the other (e.g. based on the sizes of the parts of our brains used for processing emotion, our personalities or experiences) and ignoring these differences would be the same philosophically as ignoring the differences between humans and chickens. We might learn differences that go in each direction for you and I, resulting in a moral complex cluelessness, but the same can actually happen with nonhuman animals, too: there are reasons to believe some nonhuman animals could typically experience some things more intensely than us, e.g. our better awareness of the context around an experience can reduce its intensity, and some animals have faster processing times. It’s plausible enough to me that dogs have higher highs in practice than me (although maybe I’m capable of higher highs; they just don’t happen).
Have you considered a (semi-)blind approach? Collect data on each of the species/taxa of interests into a table, but hide the species (except possibly human, as the reference?) and make moral weight judgements based on that (and the judges can do this without any formal or precise weighting of features if they prefer). You could also get separate people who do the research and prepare the table from those who make the judgements, to reduce the identifiability of the species/taxa from the data, although this risk won’t really go away.
Yeah, that’s an interesting idea. Sounds pretty good in principle, though I imagine fairly hard to implement in practice. AI Impacts did something similar last year when they investigated the relationship between neuron count and general intelligence. They prepared anonymized descriptions of the behavior of four species (two birds and two primates). Survey participants were asked to judge which animals were more intelligent on the basis of the anonymized descriptions. (The birds scored about the same as the primates.)
Appreciate the care taken, especially in the atomistic section. One thing is that it seems to assume that best we can do with such a research agenda is analyze correlates, where what we really want is a causal model.