Tort Law Can Play an Important Role in Mitigating AI Risk
Epistemic status: This is a summary of an 80-page law review article that took me ~6 months to research and write. I am highly confident about my characterization of existing U.S. tort law and its limits. This characterization is only contested by other legal scholars and analysts on the margin. My prescriptions are much more controversial, though most of the objections come from people who are skeptical of AI catastrophic risk and/or the political viability of my proposals, rather than the merits (on the assumption that advanced AI systems do generate catastrophic risks).
TLDR: Legal liability could substantially mitigate AI risk, but current law falls short in two key ways: (1) it requires provable negligence, and (2) it greatly limits the availability of punitive damages. Applying strict liability (a form of liability that does not require provable negligence) and expanding the availability and flexibility of punitive damages is feasible, but will require action by courts or legislatures. Legislatures should also consider acting in advance to create a clear ex ante expectation of liability and imposing liability insurance requirements for the training and deployment of advanced AI systems. The following post is a summary of a law review article. Here is the full draft paper. Dylan Matthews also did an excellent write-up of the core proposal for Vox’s Future Perfect vertical.
AI alignment is primarily a technical problem that will require technical solutions. But it is also a policy problem. Training and deploying advanced AI systems whose properties are difficult to control or predict generates risks of harm to third parties. In economists’ parlance, these risks are negative externalities and constitute a market failure. Absent a policy response, products and services that generate such negative externalities tend to be overproduced. In theory, tort liability should work pretty well to internalize these externalities, by forcing the companies that train and deploy AI systems to pay for the harm they cause. Unlike the sort of diffuse and hard-to-trace climate change externalities associated with greenhouse gas emissions, many AI harms are likely to be traceable to a specific system trained and deployed by specific people or companies.
Unfortunately, there are two significant barriers to using tort liability to internalize AI risk. First, under existing doctrine, plaintiffs harmed by AI systems would have to prove that the companies that trained or deployed the system failed to exercise reasonable care. This is likely to be extremely difficult to prove since it would require the plaintiff to identify some reasonable course of action that would have prevented the injury. Importantly, under current law, simply not building or deploying the AI systems does not qualify as such a reasonable precaution.
Second, under plausible assumptions, most of the expected harm caused by AI systems is likely to come in scenarios where enforcing a damages award is not practically feasible. Obviously, no lawsuit can be brought after human extinction or enslavement by misaligned AI. But even in much less extreme catastrophes where humans remain alive and in control with a functioning legal system, the harm may simply be so large in financial terms that it would bankrupt the companies responsible and no plausible insurance policy could cover the damages. This means that even if AI companies are compelled to pay damages that fully compensate the people injured by their systems in all cases where doing so is feasible, this will fall well short of internalizing the risks generated by their activities. Accordingly, these companies would still have incentives to take on too much risk in their AI training and deployment decisions.
Fortunately, there are legal tools available to overcome these two challenges. The hurdle of proving a breach of the duty of reasonable care can be circumvented by applying strict liability, meaning liability absent provable negligence, to a class of AI harms. There is some precedent for applying strict liability in this context in the form of the abnormally dangerous activities doctrine. Under this doctrine, people who engage in uncommon activities that “create a foreseeable and highly significant risk of physical harm even when reasonable care is exercised by all actors” can be held liable for harms resulting from the inherently dangerous nature of the activity, even if they exercise reasonable care. Courts could, if they are persuaded of the dangers associated with advanced AI systems, treat training and deploying AI systems with unpredictable and uncontrollable properties as an abnormally dangerous activity that falls under this doctrine. Alternatively, state legislatures could pass legislation instructing the courts in their state to apply strict liability in some specified set of AI harm cases.
The second problem of practically non-compensable harms is a bit more difficult to overcome. But tort law does have a tool that can be repurposed to handle it: punitive damages. Punitive damages impose liability on top of the compensatory damages the plaintiffs in successful lawsuits get to compensate them for the harm the defendant caused them. And one key rationale for this form of damages is that compensatory damages alone would tend to underdeter the tortious conduct involved. In the framework I propose, punitive damages could be applied in cases of practically compensable harm from AI that are correlated with uninsurable AI risks. In this way, punitive damages would pull forward the expected liability associated with uninsurable risks. Since we cannot hold AI companies responsible when uninsurable catastrophes occur, the only way to internalize uninsurable risks is to hold companies responsible for the expected harm associated with those risks before they are realized. In the next post, I will sketch out the appropriate punitive damages formula and explain how more technically oriented AI safety researchers can help lay the groundwork for implementing it.
Unfortunately, existing punitive damages law is poorly suited to the risks posed by advanced AI systems, in two ways. First, punitive damages require malicious or reckless conduct on the part of the defendant. This means that they are unavailable in cases of ordinary negligence, let alone strict liability. Second, there is no precedent for basing a punitive damages calculation on counterfactual injuries or unrealized risks. Rather punitive damages are typically used when the defendant has already caused a great deal of harm, but most of those harms are unlikely to result in successful lawsuits. Moreover, unlike with strict liability, there is no pathway for courts to carve out a narrow exception for AI, allowing punitive damages in ordinary negligence or strict liability cases involving AI, but not other harms. Eliminating the malice or recklessness requirement and allowing punitive damages calculations to account for unrealized uninsurable risk are both big asks to make of common law courts. To be clear, these are both warranted doctrinal moves that are consistent with the optimal deterrence rationale for punitive damages and within the powers of courts to make. Nonetheless, the sort of punitive damages I call for are more likely to be achieved via legislation.
If state legislature or Congress do take up AI liability legislation, this could unlock two additional important features. First, legislation could make the availability of strict liability and punitive damages clear well in advance of the first case of legally compensable harm caused by an advanced AI system. Courts, by contrast, have no means of credibly announcing their policies in advance. They can only decide cases as they come and write opinions explaining their rulings. If we are in for a hard takeoff, then there won’t be time for early AI liability cases to work their way through the courts and generate the expectation of liability needed to induce AI companies to move more slowly and cautiously in training and deploying advanced AI systems. Second, state or federal legislation could require companies that train or deploy advanced AI systems to carry liability insurance that scales with potentially dangerous system capabilities, both anticipated (in the case of training insurance requirements) or measured (in the case of deployment insurance requirements). This would introduce a more cautious decision maker, the insurance company, into the loop. Training or deployment would only be permitted if and when the AI company is able to persuade an insurance company to write it a policy it can afford. This would guard against incautious behavior on the part of AI companies whose key decision-makers either underrate AI risk or do not expect there to be many “warning shot” cases of practically compensable harm that is correlated with uninsurable risk.
If the tort law system can create an expectation that AI companies will be held liable for all of the expected harm generated by their choices, it should induce greater caution. This means both investing more in alignment and moving slower to train and deploy more capable systems. There are important limits to ex post liability, but it can play a crucial role in reducing AI risk, including catastrophic risk, if the technical, legal, and political barriers can be overcome. In a follow-up post, I explain how AI safety researchers can help address the technical barriers to implementing this framework.
- Some underrated reasons why the AI safety community should reconsider its embrace of strict liability by 8 Apr 2024 18:50 UTC; 67 points) (
- Post series on “Liability Law for reducing Existential Risk from AI” by 29 Feb 2024 4:39 UTC; 42 points) (LessWrong;
- MATS AI Safety Strategy Curriculum v2 by 7 Oct 2024 22:44 UTC; 42 points) (LessWrong;
- AI governance and strategy: a list of research agendas and work that could be done. by 12 Mar 2024 11:21 UTC; 33 points) (
- How Technical AI Safety Researchers Can Help Implement Punitive Damages to Mitigate Catastrophic AI Risk by 19 Feb 2024 17:43 UTC; 28 points) (
- AXRP Episode 28 - Suing Labs for AI Risk with Gabriel Weil by 17 Apr 2024 21:42 UTC; 12 points) (LessWrong;
- AI governance and strategy: a list of research agendas and work that could be done. by 13 Mar 2024 21:23 UTC; 7 points) (LessWrong;
This is a really good post, and something that is both complex and important. Thank you for taking the time to make it.
I think from some of the language used that this is a US-centric lean. I’m UK-based, but given the mutual common law system I think there’s some common ground to comment from. Given the jurisdictional difference none of these are criticisms or feedback, but are comparative explorations of your post with our own circumstance.
One thing I think is key from a liability perspective is the lack of IP protections for algorithms used as evidence. It may not be the case in the US, but in England & Wales there are very few (if any) intellectual property protections for algorithms once they are out in the open. This makes developers and retailers absurdly reluctant to disclose algorithms in court even if they are in the right. I think that is a niggle when it comes to using liability as a lever, and something that needs sorted.
The UK also doesn’t really have much of a punitive system in most cases, and it’s almost entirely based on “putting the individual back where they were”, with the exception of violated safety standards etc. I think using tort law is still feasible though, if we can address the IP issue and link harms more to ECHR, data law, and similar.
I don’t think there needs to be a worry about imminent existential risk to use tort law as a lever. Nuclear regulation has existential risk, but the safety standards still have plenty of punitive element there, as well as a tort law aspect. It links in with your strict liability point, but I do wonder how we would define ‘unpredictable and uncontrollable’ in terms of AI systems—though likely that is one for the guidance notes.
I do think there would be merit in compulsory insurance, and a portion of that insurance paying into a pot from which significant uninsured harms are compensated from. The UK does that with motor insurance, but other countries likely have similar systems.
Really enjoyed this post, and hope to see more from you soon.
Indeed, this post is primarily addressing U.S. tort law. I should have made that clearer.
That said, if you want to see more, I’d direct you to the full draft law review article, which is available on SSRN: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4694006
No, no additional clarity needed at all—it was obvious. I just didn’t want it to come off like I was criticising rather than saying how this could work on our side of the pond :) I’ll be sure to give that a read tonight!
Would it make a difference if the risks were insured?
Yes. If the risks are insurable (and more so if insured), then we don’t need punitive damages to mitigate them. We can rely on the prospect of compensatory damages in the event those risks are realized. Punitive damages are only needed to protect against the risk of practically non-compensable harms, for which a compensatory damages award would not be practically enforceable.