To fund research, or not to fund research, that is the question

(Cross-posted from my substack The Ethical Economist: a blog covering Economics, Ethics and Effective Altruism.)

Many people in the EA movement give their money to fund interventions that directly improve lives. Some give to corporate campaigns to reduce animal suffering. Others fund bednets to protect people from contracting malaria. Some even directly give their money to people living in poverty.

Charities such as GiveWell and the Happier Lives Institute (HLI) advise how one can fund the most effective interventions to improve the lives of humans. Interestingly, these charities never advise that one should fund research into potentially even better interventions. These charities haven’t necessarily determined that funding research is less valuable than funding existing interventions. Instead they rule out funding research a priori, restricting their analysis to evaluating existing interventions. This doesn’t seem sensible to me.

(EDIT: I was too quick to judge that HLI rules out research, please see comments. I may also have been too quick to judge this for GiveWell)

How can we decide between funding existing interventions and funding research into potentially even better interventions? In trying to answer this question I found myself developing a simple model...

Model setup

Say that, with a fixed amount of money, we can currently do units of good each time period by funding the best intervention we have available to us. Considering HLI’s recommendations, we could think of as representing the number of Wellbeing-Adjusted Life-Years (WELLBYs) gained from giving 10% of an average annual salary to StrongMinds each year. Say that we have time periods to do good in in total.

Now consider that, instead of giving to fund existing interventions, we can decide to spend time periods (where ) using our money to fund research into potentially better interventions. This could mean funding research into psychedelic treatments to improve mental health, which at least has the potential to uncover a more effective mental health intervention than the group talk therapy utilised by StrongMinds. In this research time we do no direct good, so there is an opportunity cost in that we could have been carrying out our best existing intervention instead. However, with probability we discover a better intervention than the best one we currently have, which allows us to do units of good each year (so an improvement of ). If we discover a better intervention, we can carry out this new intervention for the rest of time. If we don’t discover a better intervention, we can simply revert back to our original intervention.

Solving for the “yes research” condition

If the expected value of engaging in research and potentially finding a better intervention exceeds the value of simply carrying out our existing intervention, we should engage in research. I call this the “yes research” condition.

The value of carrying out the existing intervention is as we do units of good in each of time periods.

The value of engaging in research is a bit more complex:

  • In the research period, lasting time periods, we do no good as we are engaging in research rather than actually improving lives.

  • After the research period, with probability we have found a better intervention, allowing us to deliver units of good for the remaining time periods. With probability we didn’t find a better intervention and so revert back to delivering units of good for the remaining time periods.

  • Therefore the expected value of engaging in research is

The “yes research” condition is when the expected value of engaging in research exceeds the value of carrying out our best existing intervention. So this is:

The “yes research condition”

Plugging in some (semi-)random numbers

Let me put some numbers in to bring this to life. Let’s say that:

  • We want to fund research for 1 year ()

  • We’re looking to do good over a period of 50 years ()

  • The probability of finding a better intervention is 10% ()

  • If we do find a better intervention, we expect to do 150 units more good every year ()

  • We currently do 500 units of good every year ()

With these (semi-)random numbers the value of carrying out our existing intervention is . The expected value of engaging in research is .

so “yes research” (just).

What can we learn from this model?

I just made up some numbers and plugged them in. In reality, estimating the probability of finding a better intervention () is likely to be quite difficult, as is estimating the amount of extra good that will be done through a better intervention if it is found (). I don’t think this means the model is useless though. One could have a good go at estimating these parameters looking at the rate of progress that is being made in psychedelic research for example. I think having a go is better than ruling out further research a priori. After all, research has done wonders in the past (consider that mental health problems used to be treated by drilling holes in people’s skulls—I’m pretty glad we didn’t just fund that for the rest of time).

Even without estimated parameter values, the model can give us some useful insights. It is interesting to analyse the effect of changing some parameters whilst keeping the others constant. Remember the “yes research condition”:

  • An increase in the probability of finding a better intervention through research () increases the left hand side of the condition, working in favour of research (see appendix for proof). Intuitively this is obvious.

    • Similarly obvious is that if we think it’s impossible to find a better intervention () the left hand side cannot be greater than the right hand side and research cannot be be worth it.

  • An increase in the extra expected good done under a better intervention () also increases the left hand side of the condition, working in favour of research. This is obvious as there is more to potentially gain from research.

  • Slightly more subtly, an increase in the amount of time spent researching (), whilst keeping all other things equal, decreases the left hand side of the condition, working in favour of not researching. This is because we don’t do any good whilst researching, incurring an opportunity cost.

  • Even more subtly, an increase in the amount of time over which we can/​are looking to do good () works in favour of research (this isn’t immediately clear from the “yes research condition”—see appendix for proof). The intuition behind this is that if research finds us a better intervention, we can use this intervention for the rest of time. Even if the better intervention is only slightly better than the best one we currently have, given enough time this small improvement will make up for the fact that we did no good during our research period.

Key takeaways

My last point in the previous section is really the key takeaway. The greater the amount of time over which we can/​are looking to do good (the greater is), the more we have to gain from doing research into better interventions. This is because there is more time over which the better intervention can deliver greater benefit.

In a way, this is just classic longtermist reasoning. Finding a better intervention is kind of like moving into a better “persistent state”, as once we have discovered a better intervention we can just fund that intervention for the rest of time. Then, given an expected vastness of the future, moving into that better persistent state can really do a phenomenal amount of total good.

It’s worth noting of course that many people are not longtermists, and that these people are likely to be the ones who are donating to fund existing effective interventions, such as giving to StrongMinds. These people clearly have some reason for not being longtermist, so may not be convinced by the above longtermist reasoning. These people may only want to consider a short overall time period in which to do good (in my model choose small ), which would work against carrying out research. However, I think that there are people who are not longtermists, but who may still be interested in considering a large timeframe over which to do good (large ), which may mean they want to fund research over existing interventions. For example:

  1. People who reject longtermism due to fanaticism: Some may think that we can predictably influence the mid-far future and may not discount the future largely, but may not be a longtermist due to concern that we can only succeed in influencing the mid-far future with very small probability. Not being comfortable with being fanatical in this way, these people may prefer the certainty of doing good by giving to StrongMinds over funding longtermist interventions. Such a person may still find funding research better than giving to StrongMinds however, as carrying out research into better interventions may not be fanatical. Even if the probability of finding a better intervention is small, it’s unlikely to be crazy small. So such people may well find that they should switch from funding existing interventions to funding research.

  2. People who reject longtermism due to preferred population axiology: Some may not find it very important to reduce risks of extinction, as they have a person-affecting view of population ethics. This may cause them to reject longtermism if they think reducing the risks of extinction is the only surefire way to tractably influence the mid-far future. These people may therefore prefer giving to StrongMinds over say the Nuclear Threat Initiative. Such people may still find funding research better than giving to StrongMinds however, as improving the quality of mental health treatment remains highly valuable under most plausible person-affecting views. Most plausible person-affecting views will accept that it is important to improve the lives of people who are not alive now but who will necessarily live in the future. In this case, such a person may want to accept a very large time period over which to do good (large in my model) which works in favour of research.

So, in short, I think there could be quite a few members of the Global Health and Wellbeing community who find that funding research into potentially better interventions has higher value, given their ethical and empirical views, than helping people through existing interventions. If this is true, the current distribution of funding in the GH&W community could be due a radical shift in the pursuit of doing the most good.

Appendices

Proof of the effect of increasing the probability of finding a better intervention through research

In the What can we learn from this model? section I claimed that increasing the probability of finding a better intervention through research () works in favour of research. This is intuitively obvious, but requires some work to demonstrate mathematically.

Let’s start with the “yes research condition”:

We can show that the left hand side of the condition increases with by manipulating it and differentiating with respect to . Simple manipulation of the left hand side gives us:

Differentiating with respect to gives:

Which equals:

This is strictly positive as . Therefore increasing works in favour of research.

Proof of the effect of having more time to do good

In the What can we learn from this model? section I claimed that increasing the amount of time over which we can/​are looking to do good () works in favour of doing research. This isn’t immediately clear from the “yes research condition” as features on both the left and right hand sides of the condition. After a few algebraic steps however my claim should become clear.

Let’s start with the “yes research condition”:

Dividing each side by we get:

Both terms on the left hand side include the fraction . We can divide the top and bottom of this fraction by to get . It is clear that this term increases as increases. Therefore increasing works in favour of research.