I am a researcher at the Happier Lives Institute. In my work, I assess the cost-effectiveness of interventions in terms of subjective wellbeing.
JoelMcGuire
Joel’s response
[Michael’s response below provides a shorter, less-technical explanation.]
Summary
Alex’s post has two parts. First, what is the estimated impact of StrongMinds in terms of WELLBYs? Second, how cost-effective is StrongMinds compared to the Against Malaria Foundation (AMF)? I briefly present my conclusions to both in turn. More detail about each point is presented in Sections 1 and 2 of this comment.
The cost-effectiveness of StrongMinds
GiveWell estimates that StrongMinds generates 1.8 WELLBYs per treatment (17 WELLBYs per $1000, or 2.3x GiveDirectly[1]). Our most recent estimate[2] is 10.5 WELLBYs per treatment (62 WELLBYs per $1000, or 7.5x GiveDirectly) . This represents a 83% discount (an 8.7 WELLBYs gap)[3] to StrongMinds effectiveness[4]. These discounts, while sometimes informed by empirical evidence, are primarily subjective in nature. Below I present the discounts, and our response to them, in more detail.
Figure 1: Description of GiveWell’s discounts on StrongMinds’ effect, and their source
Notes: The graph shows the factors that make up the 8.7 WELLBY discount.
Table 1: Disagreements on StrongMinds per treatment effect (10.5 vs. 1.8 WELLBYs) and cost
Note: HLI estimates StrongMinds has an effect of 1.8 WELLBYs per household of recipient. HLI estimates that this figure is 10.5. This represents a 8.7 WELLBY gap.How do we assess GiveWell’s discounts? We summarise our position below.
Figure 2: HLI’s views on GiveWell’s total discount of 83% to StrongMind’s effects
We think there’s sufficient evidence and reason to justify the size and magnitude of 5% of GiveWell’s total discount
For ~45% of their total discount, we are sympathetic to including a discount, but we are unsure about the magnitude (generally, we think the discount would be lower). The adjustments that I think are the most plausible are:
A discount of up to 15% for conversion between depression and life-satisfaction SD.
A discount of up to 20% for loss of effectiveness at scale.
A discount of up to 5% for response biases.
Reducing the household size down to 4.8 people.
We are unsympathetic to ~35% of their total discount, because our intuitions differ, but there doesn’t appear to be sufficient existing evidence to settle the matter (i.e., household spillovers).
We think that for 15% of their total discount, the evidence that exists doesn’t seem to substantiate a discount (i.e., their discounts on StrongMind’s durability).
However, as Michael mentions in his comment, a general source of uncertainty we have is about how and when to make use of subjective discounts. We will make more precise claims about the cost-effectiveness of StrongMinds when we finalise our revision and expansion.
The cost-effectiveness of AMF
The second part of Alex’s post is asking how cost-effective is StrongMinds compared to the Against Malaria Foundation (AMF)? AMF, which prevents malaria with insecticide treated bednets, is in contrast to StrongMinds, a primarily life-saving intervention. Hence, as @Jason rightly pointed out elsewhere in the comments, its cost-effectiveness strongly depends on philosophical choices about the badness of death and the neutral point (see Plant et al., 2022). GiveWell takes a particular set of views (deprivationism with a neutral point of 0.5) that are very favourable to life saving interventions. But there are other plausible views that can change the results, and even make GiveWell’s estimate of StrongMinds seem more cost-effective than AMF. Whether you accept our original estimate of StrongMinds, or GiveWell’s lower estimate, the comparison is still incredibly sensitive to these philosophical choices. I think GiveWell is full of incredible social scientists, and I admire many of them, but I’m not sure that should privilege their philosophical intuitions.
Further research and collaboration opportunities
We are truly grateful to GiveWell for engaging with our research on StrongMinds. I think we largely agree with GiveWell regarding promising steps for future research. We’d be keen to help make many of these come true, if possible. Particularly regarding: other interventions that may benefit from a SWB analysis, household spillovers, publication bias, the SWB effects of psychotherapy (i.e. not just depression), and surveys about views on the neutral point and the badness of death. I would be delighted if we could make progress on these issues, and doubly so if we could do so together.
1. Disagreements on the cost-effectiveness of StrongMinds
HLI estimates that psychotherapy produces 10.5 WELLBYs (or 62 per $1000, 7.5x GiveDirectly) for the household of the recipient, while GiveWell estimates that psychotherapy has about a sixth of the effect, 1.8 WELLBYs (17 per $1000 or 2.3x GiveDirectly[5]). In this section, I discuss the sources of our disagreement regarding StrongMinds in the order I presented in Table 1.
1.1 Household spillover differences
Household spillovers are our most important disagreement. When we discuss the household spillover effect or ratio we’re referring to the additional benefit each non-recipient member of the household gets, as a percentage of what the main recipient receives. We first analysed household spillovers in McGuire et al. (2022), which was recently discussed here. Notably, James Snowden pointed out a mistake we made in extracting some data, which reduces the spillover ratio from 53% to 38%.
GiveWell’s method relies on:
Discounting the 38% figure citing several general reasons. (A) Specific concerns that the studies we use might overestimate the benefits because they focused on families with children that had high-burden medical conditions. (B) A shallow review of correlational estimates of household spillovers and found spillover ratios ranging from 5% to 60%.
And finally concluding that their best guess is that the spillover percentage is 15 or 20%[6], rather than 53% (what we used in December 2022) or 38% (what we would use now in light of Snowden’s analysis). Since their resulting figure is a subjective estimate, we aren’t exactly sure why they give that figure, or how much they weigh each piece of evidence.
Table 2: HLI and GiveWell’s views on household spillovers of psychotherapy
Variable
HLI
GiveWell
Explains how much difference in SM’s effect (%)
Household spillover ratio for psychotherapy
38%
15%
3 WELLBYs (34% of total gap)
Note: The household spillover for cash transfers we estimated is 86%.
I reassessed the evidence very recently—as part of the aforementioned discussion with James Snowden—and Alex’s comments don’t lead me to update my view further. In my recent analysis, I explained that I think I should weigh the studies we previously used less because they do seem less relevant to StrongMinds, but I’m unsure what to use instead. And I also hold a more favourable intuition about household spillovers for psychotherapy, because parental mental health seems important for children (e.g., Goodman, 2020).
But I think we can agree that collecting and analysing new evidence could be very important here. The data from Barker et al. (2022), a high quality RCT of the effect of CBT on the general population in Ghana (n = ~7,000) contains information on both partners’ psychological distress when one of them received cognitive behavioural therapy, so this data can be used to estimate any spousal spillover effects from psychotherapy. I am in the early stage of analysing this data[7]. There also seems to be a lot of promising primary work that could be done to estimate household spillovers alongside the effects of psychotherapy.
1.2 Conversion between measures, data sources, and units
The conversion between depression and life-satisfaction (LS) scores ties with household spillovers in terms of importance for explaining our disagreements about the effectiveness of psychotherapy. We’ve previously assumed that a one standard deviation (SD) decrease in depression symptoms (or affective mental health; MHa) is equivalent to a one SD improvement in life-satisfaction or happiness (i.e., a 1:1 conversion), see here for our previous discussion and rationale.
Givewell has two concerns with this:
Depression and life-satisfaction measures might not be sufficiently empirically or conceptually related to justify a 1:1 conversion. Because of this, they apply an empirically based 10% discount.
They are concerned that recipients of psychotherapy have a smaller variance in subjective wellbeing (SWB) than general populations (e.g., cash transfers), which leads to inflated effect sizes. They apply a 20% subjective discount to account for this.
Hence, GiveWell applied a 30% discount (see Table 4 below).
Table 3: HLI and GiveWell’s views on converting between SDs of depression and life satisfaction
Variable HLI
GiveWell
Explains what difference in SM’s effect (%)
Conversion from depression to LS 1 to 1
1 to 0.7
3 WELLBYs (34% of total)
Overall, I agree that there are empirical reasons for including a discount in this domain, but I’m unsure of its magnitude. I think it will likely be smaller than GiveWell’s 30% discount.
1.2.1 Differences between the two measures
First, GiveWell mentions a previous estimate of ours suggesting that mental health (MH) treatments[8] impact depression 11% more than SWB. Our original calculation used a naive average, but on reflection, it seems more appropriate to use a sample-size-weighted average (because of the large differences in samples between studies), which results in depression measures overestimating SWB measures by 4%, instead of 11%.
Results between depression and happiness measures are also very close in Bhat et al. (2022; n = 589), the only study I’ve found so far that looks at effects of psychotherapy on both types of measures. We can standardise the effects in two ways. Depending on the method, the SWB effects are larger by 18% or smaller by 1% than MHa effects[9]. Thus, effects of psychotherapy on depression appear to be of similar size as effects on SWB. Given these results, I think the discount due to empirical differences could be smaller than 10%, I would guess 3%.
Another part of this is that depression and life satisfaction are not the same concept. So if the scores are different, there is a further moral question about which deserves more weight. The HLI ‘house view’, as our name indicates, favours happiness (how good/bad we feel) as what matters. Further, we suspect that measures of depression are conceptually closer to happiness than measures of life satisfaction are. Hence, if push came to shove, and there is a difference, we’d care more about the depression scores, so no discount would be justified. From our conversation with Alex, we understand that the GiveWell ‘house view’ is to care more about life satisfaction than happiness. In this case, GiveWell would be correct, by their lights, to apply some reduction here.
1.2.2 Differences in variance
In addition to their 11% conversion discount, GiveWell adds another 20% discount because they think a sample of people with depression have a smaller variance in life satisfaction scores.[10] Setting aside the technical topic of why variance in variances matters, I investigated whether there are lower SDs in life satisfaction when you screen for baseline depression using a few datasets. I found that, if anything, the SDs are larger by 4% (see Table 4 below). Although I see the rationale behind GiveWell’s speculation, the evidence I’ve looked at suggests a different conclusion.
Table 4: Life-satisfaction SD depending on clinical mental health cutoff
Dataset LS SD for general pop
LS SD for dep pop
SWB SD change (gen → dep)
SWB measure
BHPS (UK, n = 7,310) 1.23
1.30
106%
LS 1-10
HILDA (AUS, n = 4,984) 1.65
1.88
114%
LS 0-10
NIDS (SA, n = 18,039) 2.43
2.38
98%
LS 1-10
Haushofer et al. 2016 (KE, n = 1,336) 1.02
1.04
102%
LS (z-score)
Average change
1.58
1.65
104%
Note: BHPS = The British Household Panel Survey, HILDA = The Household Income and Labour Dynamics Survey, NIDS = National Income Dynamics Study. LS = life satisfaction, dep = depression.
However, I’m separately concerned that SD changes in trials where recipients are selected based on depression (i.e., psychotherapy) are inflated compared to trials without such selection (i.e., cash transfers)[11].
Overall, I think I agree with GiveWell that there should be a discount here that HLI doesn’t implement, but I’m unsure of its magnitude, and I think that it’d be smaller than GiveWell’s. More data could likely be collected on these topics, particularly how much effect sizes in practice differ between life-satisfaction and depression, to reduce our uncertainty.
1.3 Loss of effectiveness outside trials and at scale
GiveWell explains their concern, summarised in the table below:
“Our general expectation is that programs implemented as part of randomized trials are higher quality than similar programs implemented at scale. [...] For example, HLI notes that StrongMinds uses a reduced number of sessions and slightly reduced training, compared to Bolton (2003), which its program is based on.48 We think this typeof modification could reduce program effectiveness relative to what is found in trials. [...] We can also see some evidence for lower effects in larger trials…”
Table 5: HLI and GiveWell’s views on an adjustment for StongMind’s losing effectiveness at scale
Variable HLI GiveWell Explains what difference in SM’s effect (%)
Loss of effect at scale discount 0% 25% 0.9 WELLBYs (10.1% of total gap)
While GiveWell provides several compelling reasons for why StongMinds efficacy will decrease as it scales, I can’t find the reason GiveWell provides for why these reasons result in a 25% discount. It seems like a subjective judgement informed by some empirical factors and perhaps from previous experience studying this issue (e.g., cases like No Lean Season). Is there any quantitative evidence that suggests that when RCT interventions scale they drop 25% in effectiveness? While GiveWell also mentions that larger psychotherapy trials have smaller effects, I assume this is driven by publication bias (discussed in Section 1.6). I’m also less sure that scaling has no offsetting benefits. I would be surprised if when RCTs are run, the intervention has all of its kinks ironed out. In fact, there’s many cases of the RCT version of an intervention being the “minimum viable product” (Karlan et al., 2016). While I think a discount here is plausible, I’m very unsure of its magnitude.
In our updated meta-analysis we plan on doing a deeper analysis of the effect of expertise and time spent in therapy, and to use this to better predict the effect of StrongMinds. We’re awaiting the results from Baird et al. which should better reflect their new strategy as StrongMinds trained but did not directly deliver the programme.
1.4 Disagreements on the durability of psychotherapy
GiveWell explains their concern summarised in the table below, “We do think it’s plausible that lay-person-delivered therapy programs can have persistent long-term effects, based on recent trials by Bhat et al. 2022 and Baranov et al. 2020. However, we’re somewhat skeptical of HLI’s estimate, given that it seems unlikely to us that a time-limited course of group therapy (4-8 weeks) would have such persistent effects. We also guess that some of the factors that cause StrongMinds’ program to be less effective than programs studied in trials (see above) could also limit how long the benefits of the program endure. As a result, we apply an 80% adjustment factor to HLI’s estimates. We view this adjustment as highly speculative, though, and think it’s possible we could update our view with more work.”
Table 6: HLI and GiveWell’s views on a discount to account for a decrease in durability
Variable HLI GiveWell Explains what difference in SM’s effect (%)
Decrease in durability 0% 20% 0.9 WELLBYs (10.1% of total gap) Since this disagreement appears mainly based on reasoning, I’ll explain why my intuitions—and my interpretation of the data—differ from GiveWell here. I already assume that StrongMinds decays 4% more each year than does psychotherapy in general (see table 3). Baranov et al. (2020) and Bhat et al. (2022) both find long-term effects that are greater than what our general model predicts. This means that we already assume a higher decay rate in general, and especially for StrongMinds than the two best long-term studies of psychotherapy suggest. I show how these studies compare to our model in Figure 3 below.
Figure 3: Effects of our model over time, and the only long-term psychotherapy studies in LMICs
Edit: I updated the figure to add the StrongMinds model, which starts with a higher effect but has a faster decay.
Baranov et al. (2020, 16 intended sessions) and Bhat et al. (2022, 6-14 intended sessions, with 70% completion rate) were both time limited. StrongMinds historically used 12 sessions (it may be 8 now) of 90 minutes[12]. Therefore, our model is more conservative than the Baranov et al. result, and closer to the Bhat et al. which has a similar range of sessions. Another reason, in favour of the duration of StrongMinds, which I mentioned in McGuire et al. (2021), is that 78% of groups continued meeting on their own at least six months after the programme formally ended.
Bhat et al. (2022) is also notable in another regard: They asked ~200 experts to predict the impact of the intervention after 4.5 years. The median prediction underestimated the effectiveness by nearly 1/3rd, which makes me inclined to weigh expert priors less here[13].
Additionally, there seems to be something double-county in GiveWell’s adjustments. The initial effect is adjusted by 0.75 for “Lower effectiveness at scale and outside of trial contexts” and the duration effect is adjusted by 0.80, also for “lower effectiveness at scale and outside of trial contexts”. Combined this is a 0.55 adjustment instead of one 0.8 adjustment. I feel like one concern should show up as one discount.
1.5 Disagreements on social desirability bias[14]
GiveWell explains their concern, which is summarised in the table below: “One major concern we have with these studies is that participants might report a lower level of depression after the intervention because they believe that is what the experimenter wants to see [...] HLI responded to this criticism [section 4.4] and noted that studies that try to assess experimenter-demand effects typically find small effects.[...] We’re not sure these tests would resolve this bias so we still include a downward adjustment (80% adjustment factor).”
Table 7: HLI and GiveWell’s views on converting between SDs of depression and life satisfaction
Variable HLI GiveWell Explains what diff in SM’s effect (%)
Social desirability bias discount 0% 20% 0.5 WELLBYs (5.1% of total gap) Participants might report bigger effects to be agreeable with the researchers (socially driven bias) or in the hopes of future rewards (cognitively driven bias; Bandiera et al., 2018), especially if they recognise the people delivering the survey to be the same people delivering the intervention[15].
But while I also worry about this issue, I am less concerned than GiveWell that response bias poses a unique threat to psychotherapy. Because if this bias exists, it seems likely to apply to all RCTs of interventions with self-reported outcomes (and without active controls). So I think the relevant question is why the propensity to response bias might differ between cash transfers and psychotherapy? Here are some possibilities:
It seems potentially more obvious that psychotherapy should alleviate depression than cash transfers should increase happiness. If so, questions about self-reported wellbeing may be more subject to bias in psychotherapy trials[16].
We could expect that the later the follow-up, the less salient the intervention is, the less likely respondents are to be biased in this way (Park & Kumar, 2022). This is one possibility that could favour cash transfers because they have relatively longer follow-ups than psychotherapy.
However, it is obvious to cash transfer participants whether they are in the treatment (they receive cash) or control conditions (they get nothing). This seems less true in psychotherapy trials where there are often active controls.
GiveWell responded to the previous evidence I cited (McGuire & Plant, 2021, Section 4.4)[17] by arguing that the tests run in the literature, by investigating the effect of the general propensity towards socially desirable responding or the expectations of surveyor, are not relevant because: “If the surveyor told them they expected the program to worsen their mental health or improve their mental health, it seems unlikely to overturn whatever belief they had about the program’s expected effect that was formed during their group therapy sessions.” But, if participants’ views about an intervention seem unlikely to be overturned by what the surveyor seems to want—when what the surveyor wants and the participant’s experience differs—then that’s a reason to be less concerned about socially motivated response bias in general.
However, I am more concerned with socially desirable responses driven by cognitive factors. Bandiera et al. (2018, p. 25) is the only study I found to discuss the issue, but they do not seem to think this was an issue with their trial: “Cognitive drivers could be present if adolescent girls believe providing desirable responses will improve their chances to access other BRAC programs (e.g. credit). If so, we might expect such effects to be greater for participants from lower socioeconomic backgrounds or those in rural areas. However, this implication runs counter to the evidence in Table A5, where we documented relatively homogenous impacts across indices and time periods, between rich/poor and rural/urban households.”
I agree with GiveWell that more research would be very useful, and could potentially update my views considerably, particularly with respect to the possibility of cognitively driven response bias in RCTs deployed in low-income contexts.
1.6 Publication bias
GiveWell explains their concern, which we summarise in the table below: “HLI’s analysis includes a roughly 10% downward adjustment for publication bias in the therapy literature relative to cash transfers literature. We have not explored this in depth but guess we would apply a steeper adjustment factor for publication bias in therapy relative to our top charities. After publishing its cost-effectiveness analysis, HLI published a funnel plot showing a high level of publication bias, with well-powered studies finding smaller effects than less-well-powered studies.57 This is qualitatively consistent with a recent meta-analysis of therapy finding a publication bias of 25%.”
Table 8: HLI and GiveWell’s views on a publication bias discount
Variable HLI GiveWell Explains what diff in SM’s effect (%)
Publication bias discount 11% 15% 0.39 WELLBYs (4.5% of total gap) After some recent criticism, we have revisited this issue and are working on estimating the bias empirically. Publication bias seems like a real issue, where a 10-25% correction like what GiveWell suggests seems plausible, but we’re unsure about the magnitude as our research is ongoing. In our update of our psychotherapy meta-analysis we plan to employ a more sophisticated quantitative approach to adjust for publication bias.
1.7 Household size
GiveWell explains their concern, which we summarise in the table below: “HLI estimates household size using data from the Global Data Lab and UN Population Division. They estimate a household size of 5.9 in Uganda based on these data, which appears to be driven by high estimates for rural household size in the Global Data Lab data, which estimate a household size of 6.3 in rural areas in 2019. A recent Uganda National Household Survey, on the other hand, estimates household size of 4.8 in rural areas. We’re not sure what’s driving differences in estimates across these surveys, but our best guess is that household size is smaller than the 5.9 estimate HLI is using.”
Table 9: HLI and GiveWell’s views on household size of StrongMind’s recipients
Variable HLI GiveWell Explains what diff in SM’s effect (%)
Household size for StrongMinds 5.9 4.8 0.39 WELLBYs (4.5% of total gap) I think the figures GiveWell cites are reasonable. I favour using international datasets because I assume it means greater comparability between countries, but I don’t feel strongly about this. I agree it could be easy and useful to try and understand StrongMinds recipient’s household sizes more directly. We will revisit this in our StrongMinds update.
1.8 Cost per person of StrongMinds treated
The one element where we differ that makes StrongMinds look more favourable is cost. As GiveWell explains “HLI’s most recent analysis includes a cost of $170 per person treated by StrongMinds, but StrongMinds cited a 2022 figure of $105 in a recent blog post”
Table 10: HLI and GiveWell’s views on cost per person for StrongMind’s treatment
Variable HLI GiveWell % Total Gap Explained cost per person of StrongMinds $170 $105 -75% According to their most recent quarterly report, a cost per person of $105 was the goal, but they claim $74 per person for 2022[18]. We agree this is a more accurate/current figure, and the cost might well be lower now. A concern is that the reduction in costs comes at the expense of treatment fidelity – an issue we will review in our updated analysis.
2. GiveWell’s cost-effectiveness estimate of AMF is dependent on philosophical views
GiveWell estimates that AMF produces 70 WELLBYs per $1000[19], which would be 4 times better than StrongMinds. GiveWell described the philosophical assumptions of their life saving analysis as: “...Under the deprivationist framework and assuming a “neutral point” of 0.5 life satisfaction points. [...] we think this is what we would use and it seems closest to our current moral weights, which use a combination of deprivationism and time-relative interest account.”
Hence, they conclude that AMF produces 70 WELLBYs per $1000, which makes StrongMinds 0.24 times as cost-effective as AMF. However, the position they take is nearly the most favourable one can take towards interventions that save lives[20]. But there are other plausible views about the neutral point and the badness of death (we discuss this in Plant et al., 2022). Indeed, assigning credences to higher neutral points[21] or alternative philosophical views of death’s badness will reduce the cost-effectiveness of AMF relative to StrongMinds (see Figure 3). In some cases, AMF is less cost-effective than GiveWell’s estimate of StrongMinds[22].
Figure 4: Cost-effectiveness of charities under different philosophical assumptions (with updated StrongMinds value, and GiveWell’s estimate for StrongMinds)
To be clear, HLI does not (yet) take a stance on these different philosophical views. While I present some of my views here, these do not represent HLI as a whole.
Personally, I’d use a neutral point closer to 2 out of 10[23]. Regarding the philosophy, I think my credences would be close to uniformly distributed across the Epicurean, TRIA, and deprivationist views. If I plug this view into our model introduced in Plant et al. (2022) then this would result in a cost-effectiveness for AMF of 29 WELLBYs per $1000 (rather than 81 WELLBYs per $1000)[24], which is about half as good as the 62 WELLBYs per $1000 for StrongMinds. If GiveWell held these views, then AMF would fall within GiveWell’s pessimistic and optimistic estimates of 3-57 WELLBYs per $1000 for StrongMinds’ cost-effectiveness. For AMF to fall above this range, you need to (A) put almost all your credence in deprivationism and (B) have a neutral point lower than 2[25].
- ^
Coincidently, this is (barely) within our most recent confidence interval for comparing the cost-effectiveness of StrongMinds to GiveDirectly (95% CI: 2, 100).
- ^
This calculation is based on a correction for a mistake in our spillover ratio discussed here (a spillover ratio of 38% instead of 53%). Our previous estimate was 77 WELLBYs per $1000 (Plant et al., 2022; McGuire et al., 2022).
- ^
The discount on the effect per $1000 is smaller because GiveWell used a 38% smaller cost figure.
- ^
Note that the reduction in cost-effectiveness is only 27% because they also think that the costs are 62% smaller.
- ^
Coincidently, this is (barely) within our most recent confidence interval for comparing the cost-effectiveness of StrongMinds to GiveDirectly (95% CI: 2, 100).
- ^
The text and the table give different values.
- ^
But if you want to accept that the results could be very off, see here for a document with tables with my very preliminary results.
- ^
These are positive psychology interventions (like mindfulness and forgiveness therapy) which might not completely generalise to psychotherapy in LMICs.
- ^
Psychotherapy improved happiness by 0.38 on a 1-10 score and reduced depression by 0.97 (on the PHQ-9’s 0-27 scale). If we convert the depression score to a 1-10 scale, using stretch transformation, then the effect is a reduction in depression of 0.32. Hence, the SWB changes are 18% larger than MHa changes. If we convert both results to Cohen’s d, we find a Cohen’s d of 0.167 for depression and a Cohen’s d of 0.165 for happiness. Hence changes in MHa are 1% greater than SWB.
- ^
“it seems likely that SD in life satisfaction score is lower among StrongMinds recipients, who are screened for depression at baseline46 and therefore may be more concentrated at the lower end of the life satisfaction score distribution than the average individual.”
- ^
Sample selection based on depression (i.e., selection based on the outcome used) could shrink the variance of depression scores in the sample, which would inflate standardised effects sizes of depression compared to trials without depression selection, because standardisation occurs by dividing the raw effect by its standard deviation (i.e., standardised mean differences, such as Cohen’s d). To explore this, I used the datasets mentioned in Table 4, all of which also included measures of depression or distress and the data from Barker et al. (2022, n = 11,835). I found that the SD of depression for those with clinically significant depression was 18 to 21% larger than it was for the general sample (both the mentally ill and healthy). This seems to indicate that SD changes from psychotherapy provide inflated SD changes in depression compared to cash transfers, due to smaller SDs of depression. However, I think this may be offset by another technical adjustment. Our estimate of the life-satisfaction SD we use to convert SD changes (in MHa or SWB) to WELLBYs might be larger, which means the effects of psychotherapy and cash transfers are underestimated by 14% compared to AMF. When we convert from SD-years to WELLBYs we’ve used a mix of LMIC and HIC sources to estimate the general SD of LS. But I realised that there’s a version of the World Happiness Report that published data that included the SDs of LS for many countries in LMICs. If we use this more direct data for Sub-Saharan Countries then it suggests a higher SD of LS than what I previously estimated (2.5 instead of 2.2, according to a crude estimate), a 14% increase.
- ^
In one of the Bhat et al. trials, each session was 30 to 45 minutes (it’s unclear what the session length was for the other trials).
- ^
Note, I was one of the predictors, and my guess was in line with the crowd (~0.05 SDs), and you can’t see others’ predictions beforehand on the Social Science Prediction Platform.
- ^
Note, this is more about ‘experimenter demand effects’ (i.e., being influenced by the experimenters in a certain direction, because that’s what they want to find) than ‘socially desirability bias’ (i.e., answering that one is happier than they are because it looks better). The latter is controlled for in an RCT. We keep the wording used by GW here.
- ^
GiveWell puts it in the form of this scenario “If a motivated and pleasant IPT facilitator comes to your village and is trying to help you to improve your mental health, you may feel some pressure to report that the program has worked to reward the effort that facilitator has put into helping you.” But these situations are why most implementers in RCTs aren’t the surveyors. I’d be concerned if there were more instances of implementers acting as surveyors in psychotherapy than cash transfer studies.
- ^
On the other hand, who in poverty expects cash transfers to bring them misery? That seems about as rare (or rarer) as those who think psychotherapy will deepen their suffering. However, I think the point is about what participants think that implementers most desire.
- ^
Since then, I did some more digging. I found Dhar et al. (2018) and Islam et al. (2022) which use a questionnaire to test for propensity to answer questions in a socially desirable manner, but find similarly small results of socially motivated response bias. Park et al. (2022) takes an alternative approach where they randomise a subset of participants to self-survey, and argue that this does not change the results.
- ^
This is mostly consistent with 2022 expenses / people treated = 8,353,149 / 107,471 = $78.
- ^
81 WELLBYs per $1000 in our calculations, but they add some adjustments.
- ^
The most favourable position would be assuming deprivationism and a neutral point of zero.
- ^
People might hold that the neutral point is higher than 0.5 (on a 0-10 scale), and thereby reduce the cost-effectiveness of AMF. The IDinsight survey GiveWell uses surveys people from Kenya and Ghana but has a small sample (n = 70) for its neutrality question. In our pilot report (n = 79; UK sample; Samuelsson et al., 2023) we find a neutral point of 1.3. See Samuelsson et al. (2023; Sections 1.3 and 6) for a review of the different findings in the literature and more detail on our findings. Recent unpublished work by Julian Jamison finds a neutral point of 2.5 on a sample size of ~1,800 drawn from the USA, Brazil and China. Note that, in all these cases, we recommend caution in concluding that any of these values is the neutral point. There is still more work to be done.
- ^
Under GiveWell’s analysis, there are still some combinations of philosophical factors where AMF produces 17 WELLBYs or less (i.e., is as or less good than SM in GiveWell’s analysis): (1) An Epicurean view, (2) Deprivationism with neutral points above 4, and (3) TRIA with high ages of connectivity and neutral points above 3 or 4 (depending on the combination). This does not include the possibility of distributing credences across different views.
- ^
I would put the most weight on the work by HLI and Jamison and colleagues, mentioned in above, which finds a neutral point of 1.3/10 and 2.5/10, respectively.
- ^
I average the results across each view.
- ^
We acknowledge that many people may hold these views. We also want to highlight that many people may hold other views. We encourage more work investigating the neutral point and investigating the extent to which these philosophical views are held.
- EA EDA: Looking at Forum trends across 2023 by Jun 11, 2024, 6:34 PM; 103 points) (
- Mar 24, 2023, 2:26 PM; 41 points) 's comment on Assessment of Happier Lives Institute’s Cost-Effectiveness Analysis of StrongMinds by (
- Jul 13, 2023, 5:21 PM; 34 points) 's comment on The Happier Lives Institute is funding constrained and needs you! by (
- Mar 22, 2023, 9:59 PM; 29 points) 's comment on Assessment of Happier Lives Institute’s Cost-Effectiveness Analysis of StrongMinds by (
- StrongMinds (5 of 9) - Depression’s Moral Weight by Dec 24, 2023, 11:51 AM; 26 points) (
Joel from HLI here,
Alex kindly shared a draft of this report and discussed feedback from Michael and I more than a year ago. He also recently shared this version before publication. We’re very pleased to finally see that this is published!
We will be responding in more (maybe too much) detail tomorrow. I’m excited to see more critical discussion of this topic.
I’d assume that 1. you don’t need the whole household, depending on the original sample size, it seems plausible to randomly select a subset of household members [1](e.g., in house A you interview recipient and son, in B. recipient and partner, etc...) and 2. they wouldn’t need to consent to participate, just to be surveyed, no?
If these assumptions didn’t hold, I’d be more worried that this would introduce nettlesome selection issues.
- ^
I recognise this isn’t necessarily simple as I make it out to be. I expect you’d need to be more careful with the timing of interviews to minimise the likelihood that certain household members are more likely to be missing (children at school, mother at the market, father in the fields, etc.).
- ^
Given that this post has been curated, I wanted to follow up with a few points I’d like to emphasise that I forgot to include in the original comment.
To my knowledge, we were the first to attempt to estimate household spillovers empirically. In hindsight, it shouldn’t be too surprising that it’s been a messy enterprise. I think I’ve updated towards “messiness will continue”.
One hope of ours in the original report was to draw more attention to the yawning chasm of good data on this topic.
“The lack of data on household effects seems like a gap in the literature that should be addressed by further research. We show that including household spillovers can change the relative cost-effectiveness of two interventions, which demonstrates the need to account for the impact of interventions beyond the direct recipient.”
Relatedly, spillovers don’t have to be huge to be important. If you have a household of 5, with 1 recipient and 4household non-recipients, household spillovers only need to be 25% that of the recipient effect for the two effects to be equivalent in size. I’m still pretty confident we omit an important parameter when we fail to estimate household spillovers.
So I’m pleased with this conversation and hopeful that spillovers for all outcomes in the global health and wellbeing space will be given more empirical consideration as a consequence.
There are probably relatively cost-effective ways to gather more data regarding psychotherapy spillovers in particular.
I’ve heard that some people working with Vida-Plena are trying to find funding for an RCT that includes spillovers — but I haven’t spoken to Joy about this recently.
StrongMinds could be willing to do more work here. I think they’re planning an RCT — if they get it funded, I think adding a module for household surveys shouldn’t be too expensive.
There’s also a slew of meta-analyses of interventions aimed at families that didn’t always seem jointly to target parents and children that may include more RCTs where we can infer spillovers. Many of these I missed before: Siegenthaler et al. (2012), Thanhäuser et al. (2017), Yap et al. (2016), Loechner et al. (2018), Lannes et al., (2018), and Havinga et al. (2021)
In general, household spillovers should be relatively cheap to estimate if they just involve surveying a randomly selected additional household member and clarifying the relationships between those surveyed.
I still don’t have the Barker et al. RCT spillover results, but will update this comment once I know.
- Jul 9, 2023, 4:28 PM; 14 points) 's comment on The Happier Lives Institute is funding constrained and needs you! by (
- Jul 10, 2023, 10:30 PM; 8 points) 's comment on The Happier Lives Institute is funding constrained and needs you! by (
Neat! Cover jacket could use a graphic designer in my opinion. It’s also slotted under engineering? Am I missing something?
Dear Srdjan,
I think we do address the potential for negative impacts. As we say in section 2.2 (and elaborate on in Appendix B.3:
“From 11 studies we estimate that a 1% increase in immigrants as a share of the population is associated with a (non-significant) decrease of −0.004 SDs of SWB (or −0.008 WELLBYs) for the native population.”
Additionally, we have a subsection (3.2) called “risk of backlash effects”. Again, these may not be the concerns you have in mind, but to say we’re only mentioning positive effects is wrong. We mention throughout the report that we’re concerned with potential negative impacts and include speculative estimates of these in our BOTECs.
And in section B.2 we say
One concern is that emigration could limit the ability of the origin country to improve its institutions. This could be true if emigration drains high-skilled individuals from the country, making it poorer and less likely to reform. We expect this concern to be blunted somewhat by high rates of return (29% globally, Azose & Raftery, 2018) and remittances (which are three times the size of development aid). Remittances seem correlated to beneficial political (Williams, 2018) and economic (Yoshino et al., 2017; Kratou et al., 2015) effects at the country level. Historical quasi-experimental evidence from Sweden found that Swedish emigration led to a higher likelihood of reform for local governments in Sweden (Karadja & Prawitz, 2019). However, this study may not generalise to other contexts. We think that the positive effects of emigration may be less likely in authoritarian countries where potential reformers may emigrate at higher rates.
James courteously shared a draft of this piece with me before posting, I really appreciate that and his substantive, constructive feedback.
1. I blundered
The first thing worth acknowledging is that he pointed out a mistake that substantially changes our results. And for that, I’m grateful. It goes to show the value of having skeptical external reviewers.
He pointed out that Kemp et al., (2009) finds a negative effect, while we recorded its effect as positive — meaning we coded the study as having the wrong sign.
What happened is that MH outcomes are often “higher = bad”, and subjective wellbeing is “higher = better”, so we note this in our code so that all effects that imply benefits are positive. What went wrong was that we coded Kemp et al., (2009), which used the GHQ-12 as “higher = bad” (which is usually the case) when the opposite was true. Higher equalled good in this case because we had to do an extra calculation to extract the effect [footnote: since there was baseline imbalance in the PHQ-9, we took the difference in pre-post changes], which flipped the sign.
This correction would reduce the spillover effect from 53% to 38% and reduce the cost-effectiveness comparison from 9.5 to 7.5x, a clear downwards correction.
This is how the forest plot should look.
2. James’s other critiques
I think James’s other critiques are also pretty reasonable. This updates me towards weighting these studies less. That said, what I should place weight on instead remains quite uncertain for me.
I’ve thought about it a bit, but I’m unsure what to make of the observational evidence. My reading of the observational literature mostly accords with James (I think), and it does appear to suggest smaller spillovers than the low quality RCTs I previously referenced (20% versus the now 38%). Here’s a little table I made while doing a brief review during my discussion with James.
Study Shock type Study type Relationship Spillover adjusted Spillover raw Genetic / sorting discount Powdthavee & Vignoles (2008) MH time lagged panel mother to spouse 0.00%
0.00%
25%[1]
Webb et al., (2017) MH time lagged panel mother to spouse 5.25%
7.00%
25%
Chi et al., (2019) MH time lagged panel mother to spouse 22.50%
30.00%
25%
Mcnamee et al., (2021) MH correlational (?) spouse to spouse 3.75%
5.00%
25%
Das et al., (2008) MH correlational any HH dyad (imputed)[2] 10.00%
40.00%
50%[3]
Average 7.88%
Powdthavee & Vignoles (2008) MH time lagged panel mother to child 10.50%
14.00%
25%
Webb et al., (2017) MH time lagged panel mother to child 12.00%
16.00%
25%
Chi et al., (2019) MH time lagged panel mother to child 43.50%
58.00%
25%
Das et al., (2008) MH correlational any HH dyad (imputed) 40.00%
40.00%
50%
Eyal & Burns (2018) MH correlational parent to child 16.50%
33.00%
50%
Average 24.50%
Implied HH spillover 20.34%
Esche (2020) Unemp time lagged panel spouse to spouse 31.50%
35.00%
10%
Nikolova & Ayhan (2019) Unemp Quasi- experiment spouse to spouse 35.00%
35.00%
0%
Hurd et al. (2014) Reemp time lagged panel spouse to spouse 34.00%
34.00%
0%
Hurd et al. (2014) Unemp time lagged panel spouse to spouse 60.00%
60.00%
0%
Average 40.13%
Nikolova & Nikolaev (2021) Unemp Quasi- experiment parent to child 63.00%
63.00%
0%
Average 63.00%
Implied HH spillover 57.28%
However, I wonder if there’s something about the more observational literature that makes household spillovers appear smaller, regardless of the source. To investigate this further, I briefly compared household spillovers from unemployment and mental health shocks. This led me to an estimate of around 57% as the household spillover of unemployment, which I think we could use as a prior for other economic shocks. This is a bit lower than the 86% I estimated as the household spillover for cash transfers. Again, not quite sure what to make of this.
3. Other factors that influence my priors / fuzzy tummy feelings about psychotherapy spillovers.
Mother’s mental health seems really important, over and above a father’s mental health. Augustijn (2022) finds a higher relationship between mother<> child MH than father<>child mental health (a 1 LS point change in the mother predicts a 0.13 change in LS for child (as compared to 0.06 for fathers). Many of the studies above seem to have larger mother → child effects than father → child. This could be relevant as StrongMinds primarily treats women.
Mental health appears important relative to the effect of income.
See figure from Clark et al., (2018) -- shown below.
Mcnamee et al., (2021) (published version of Mendolia et al., 2018) finds that having a partner with a long term emotional or nervous condition that requires treatment has a −0.08 effect on LS, and that log household income has a 0.064 effect. If we interpret 0.69 log-units as leading to a doubling, and assume that most $1000 CTs lead to about a doubling in household income, then the effect of doubling income is 0.064 * 0.69 = 0.04 effect on LS. If I assume that the effect of depression is similar to “long-term emotional or nervous condition that requires treatment” and psychotherapy cures 40% of depression cases, then this leads to an effect of psychotherapy of 0.4 * −0.08 = 0.032. Or the effect of psychotherapy relative to doubling the income on a partner is 73%. Applying this to the 86% CT spillover would get us a 63% spillover ratio for psychotherapy.
You could compare income and mental health effects on wellbeing in other studies—but I haven’t had time to do so (and I’m not really sure of how informative this is).
Powdthavee & Vignoles (2008), which found the effect of mother distress in the previous period on children is 14% of the effect that the child’s own wellbeing in the previous period had on their present wellbeing. But it also seems to give weirdly small coefficients (and non-significant) for the effect of log-income on life satisfaction (0.054 for fathers, negative −0.132 for mothers).
Early life exposure to a parent’s low mental health seems plausibly related to very long term wellbeing effects through higher likelihood of worse parenting (abuse, fewer resources to support the child; Zheng et al., 2021)
I’m unsure if positive and negative shocks spillover in the same way. Negativity seems more contagious than positivity. For instance in Hurd et al. (2014) the spillover effects of re-employment seemed less than the harms of unemployment. Also see Adam et al., (2014)[4] – I’m sure there’s much more on this topic. This makes me think that it may not be wild to see a relatively smaller gap between the spillovers of cash transfers and psychotherapy than we may initially expect.
Most of these studies are in HICs. It seems plausible that spillovers for any intervention could be different and I suspect higher in LMICs than HICs. I assume emotional contagion is a function of spending time together, and spending more time together seems likelier when houses are smaller (you can’t shut yourself in your room as easily), transportation is relatively more expensive, difficult, and dangerous – and you may have fewer reasons to go elsewhere. One caveat is that household sizes are larger, so there may be less time directly spent with any given household member, so that’s a factor that could push in the other direction.
4. What’s next?
I think James and I probably agree that making sense out of the observational evidence is tricky to say the least, and a high quality RCT would be very welcome for informing our views and settling our disagreements. I think some further insight could come sooner rather than later. As I was writing this, I wondered if there was any possibility of household spillovers in Barker et al., (2022), a recent study about the effects of CBT on the general population in Ghana that looked into community spillovers of psychotherapy (-33% the size of the treatment effect but non-significant – but’s that’s a problem for another time).
In section 3.2 the paper reads, “At the endline we administered only the “adult” survey, again to both the household head and their spouse… In our analysis of outcomes, we include the responses of both adults in control households; in households where an individual received CBT, we only include treated individuals.’”
This means that while Barket et al. didn’t look into it we should be able to estimate the spousal mental health spillover of having your partner receive CBT. In further good news, the replication materials are public. But I’ll leave this as a teaser while I try to figure out how to run the analysis.
- ^
Why a 25% discount? I guess partners are likelier to share tendencies towards a given level of wellbeing, but I think this “birds of a feather” effect is smaller than the genetic effects. Starting from a 50% guess for genetic effects (noted in the next footnote), I thought that the assortative mating effects would be about half the magnitude or 25%.
- ^
How did I impute the parent/child effect? The study was ambiguous about the household relations being analysed. So I assumed that it was 50-50 parents and children and that the spouse-to-spouse spillover was a 1/4th that of the parent-to-child spillover.
- ^
Why a 50% discount? There appears to be an obvious genetic factor between a parent and child’s levels of wellbeing that could confound these estimates. Jami et al., (2021) reviews ~30 studies that try to disentangle the genetic and environmental link between families affective mental health. My reading is that environmental (pure contagion) effects dominate the anxiety transmission, and genetic-environmental factors seem roughly balanced for depression. Since we mostly consider psychotherapy to treat depression, I only reference the depression results when coming up with the 50% figure.
- ^
“When positive posts were reduced in the News Feed, the percentage of positive words in people’s status updates decreased by B = −0.1% compared with control [t(310,044) = −5.63, P < 0.001, Cohen’s d = 0.02], whereas the percentage of words that were negative increased by B = 0.04% (t = 2.71, P = 0.007, d = 0.001). Conversely, when negative posts were reduced, the percent of words that were negative decreased by B = −0.07% [t(310,541) = −5.51, P < 0.001, d = 0.02] and the percentage of words that were positive, conversely, increased by B = 0.06% (t = 2.19, P < 0.003, d = 0.008).
- Run Posts By Orgs by Mar 29, 2023, 2:40 AM; 281 points) (
- Assessment of Happier Lives Institute’s Cost-Effectiveness Analysis of StrongMinds by Mar 22, 2023, 5:04 PM; 243 points) (
- Jul 10, 2023, 3:28 PM; 58 points) 's comment on The Happier Lives Institute is funding constrained and needs you! by (
- On what basis did Founder’s Pledge disperse $1.6 mil. to Qvist Consulting from its Climate Change Fund? by Mar 27, 2023, 3:26 AM; 39 points) (
- Jul 25, 2023, 6:19 PM; 19 points) 's comment on The Happier Lives Institute is funding constrained and needs you! by (
- Feb 26, 2023, 6:41 PM; 18 points) 's comment on Why I don’t agree with HLI’s estimate of household spillovers from therapy by (
- Run Posts By Orgs by Mar 29, 2023, 2:40 AM; 16 points) (LessWrong;
- Mar 24, 2023, 12:46 AM; 6 points) 's comment on Assessment of Happier Lives Institute’s Cost-Effectiveness Analysis of StrongMinds by (
The guess is based on a recent (unpublished and not sure I can cite) survey that I think did the best job yet at eliciting people’s views on the neutral point in three countries (two LMICs).
I agree it’s a big ask to get people to use the exact same scales. But I find it reassuring that populations who we wouldn’t be surprised as having the best and worst lives tend to rate themselves as having about the best and worst lives that a 0 to 10 scale allows (Afghanis at ~2/10 and Finns at ~8/10.
That’s not to dismiss the concern. I think it’s plausible that there are systematic differences in scale use (non-systematic differences would wash out statistically). Still, I think people self-reporting about their wellbeing is informative enough to find and fix the issues rather than give up.
For those somehow interested in this nerdy aside, for further reading see Kaiser & Oswald (2022) on whether subjective scales behave how we’d expect (they do), Plant (2020) on the comparability of subjective scales, and Kaiser & Vendrik (2022) on how threatened subjective scales are to divergences from the linearity assumption (not terribly).
Full disclosure: I’m a researcher at the Happier Lives Institute, which does cause prioritization research using subjective well-being data, so it’s probably not surprising I’m defending the use of this type of data.
Trying to hold onto the word “eugenics” seems to indicate an unrealistically optimistic belief in people’s capacity to tolerate semantics. Letting go is a matter of will, not reason.
E.g., I pity the leftist who thinks they can, in every conversation with a non-comrade, explain the difference between the theory of a classless society, the history of ostensibly communist regimes committing omnicide, and the hitherto unrealised practice of “real communism” (outside of a few scores of 20th-century Israeli villages and towns). To avoid the reverse problem when discussing “communist” regimes, I refer to “authoritarian regimes with command economies”. And I’m convinced it’s almost always better to go with “Social Democracy”.
Who cares if no other word has caught on yet. Marketing is a great and powerful force (one EAs seem only dimly to understand). Use more words if you have to. The key point is that “it’s a good idea to avoid tying yourself to words where the most common use is associated with mass murder.” [1]
Turning to the example. I’d pray to Hedone that most EAs can read the room well enough to avoid making such arguments while we still have nuclear wars to stop, pandemics to prevent, diseases to cure, global poverty to stamp out, and many cheap and largely uncontroversial treatments for depression and everyday sadness we’ve yet to scale. But assuming they did make that argument, I think the response to “That’s eugenics” should be something like:
“No, eugenics is associated with stripping a group of people of their right to reproduce. I’m discussing supporting families to make choices about their children’s health. Screening is already supported for many debilitating health conditions because of the suffering they produce, I’m saying that we should provide that same support when the conditions that produce the suffering are mental rather than physical.”
But maybe a takeaway here is: “don’t feed the trolls”?
- ^
Note: One response is, “we can’t give up on every word once it’s tainted by associated with some unseemly set of disreputes.” And that’s fair. For instance, I’m fine being associated with “Happiness Science” because the most common use is associated with social science into self-reported wellbeing, not a genocide-denying Japanese cult. The point is that choice of association depends on what most people associate the word with. Language will always be more bottom-up than top-down and seems much closer to a rowdy democracy than a sober technocracy.
- ^
A note on the “positive utility” bit. I am very uncertain about this. We don’t really know where on subjective wellbeing scales people construe wellbeing to go from positive to negative. My best bet is around 2.5 on a 0 to 10 scale. This would indicate that ~18% of people in SSA or South Asia have lives with negative wellbeing if what we care about is life satisfaction (debatable). For the world, this means 11%, which is similar to McAskill’s guess of 10% in WWOTF.
And insofar as happiness is separate from life satisfaction. It’s very rare for a country, on average, to report being more unhappy than happy.
I haven’t downvoted or read the post, but one explanation is the title “You’re probably a eugenicist” seems clickbaity and aimed at persuasion. It reads as ripe for plucking out of context by our critics. I immediately see it cited in the next major critique published in a major news org: “In upvoted posts on the EA forum, EAs argue they can have ‘reasonable’ conversations about eugenics.”
One idea for dealing with controversial ideas is to A. use a different word and or B. make it more boring. If the title read something like, “Most people favor selecting for valuable hereditary traits.” My pulse would quicken less upon reading.
I dont see this as much of an update. Mutual inspections under the treaty haven‘t taken place for a year, it’s basically already been suspended since the invasion. I would be more concerned if he formally withdrew, but he didn’t even do that.
In retrospect, I think my reply didn’t do enough to acknowledge that A. using a different starting value seems reasonable and B. this would lead to a much smaller change in cost-effectiveness foor deworming. While very belated, I’m updating the post to note this for posterity.
I agree that advocacy for high skilled immigration is more likely to succeed, and that the benefits would probably come more from technological and material progress. The problem is we currently aren’t prepared to try and estimate the benefits of these society and world wide spillover effects.
Maybe we will return to this if (big if) we explore policies that may cost-effectively increase GDP growth (which some argue is = tech progress in the long run?), and through that subjective wellbeing [1] .
Regarding Malengo, I asked Johannes a few questions about it and I’m referencing that post whenever I cite Malengo numbers. I didn’t add it here because most of our work was already done when they wrote a post about it, and I was too lazy, and I didn’t think it looked particularly promising in my initial estimates. However, I now notice that in my previous calculations I didn’t consider remittances, which seems like an omission. As we discussed in the report, it’s unclear how remittances balance the negative effects of separation from the immigrant, but I think that separation pains are less of a concern if it’s a young adult leaving—as that’s pretty normal in many cultures.
So here’s a BOTEC with remittances considered.
As Johannes said, they expect that 64% of students will settle permanently in Germany (or a similar country) after graduating. I interpret this to imply an expected stay of 38.4 years, which if life-satisfaction difference between the countries closes slightly to 2 life-satisfaction points, will mean 2 * 38.4 = 78.8 WELLBYs per student sent. It costs $15,408 [2]to fund a student to matriculate in Germany.
If we’re only concerned with the student, this implies a cost-effectiveness of 76.8 / $15,408 = ~5 WELLBYs per $1000. Which is a bit less than 8 WELLBYs per $1k that I estimate come from GiveDirectly cash transfers. But this excludes remittances.
They expect Malengo participants to remit ~$2k a year. If assume a 1 to 1 equivalence between $1k of remittances and GiveDirectly cash transfers, and assume this continues for 20 years, this would imply a 40 * 8 = 320 additional WELLBYs generated by remittances. This boosts the cost-effectiveness of Malengo from ~0.6x GiveDirectly to ~3x GiveDirectly. However, I’m unsure that the equivalence assumption would be warranted, or how long we could expect remittances to continue[3]. One potential concern is that the families that can send students to university (regardless of cost) are going to be much wealthier, so remittances will matter relatively less.
- ^
Note that the relationship between GDP <> SWB is rather contested—see previous work from HLI on the topic that argues that maybe GDP doesn’t matter much for subjective wellbeing, and a reply post from Founder’s Pledge that argues against that point using the same evidence. In the latter post there’s also a quite interesting discussion Vadim and an author of one of the key papers (Kelsey O’Connor).
- ^
Malengo costs 12k euros to send a student, and they hope to get overhead down to 20% once they scale. Converting this into dollars implies $15k.
- ^
This question should be easy in principle, to gain traction on. We could use a survey that includes immigrants that asks about if they send remittances, and how long they’ve lived in the country they moved to.
- ^
Immigration reform: a shallow cause exploration
Thanks, great reply!
Hi David, I’m excited about this! It certainly seems like a step in the right direction. A few vague questions that I’m hoping you’ll divine my meaning from:
Maybe this is redundant with Gideon’s question, but I’d like to press further on this. What is the “depth” of research you think is best suited for the Unjournal? It seems like the vibe is “at least econ working paper level of rigor”. But it seems like a great amount of EA work is shallower, or more weirdly formatted than a working paper. I.e., Happier Lives Insitute reports are probably a bit below that level of depth (and we spend a lot more time than many others) and GiveWell’s CEAs have no dedicated write-ups. Would either of these research projects be suitable for the Unjournal?
It seems like the answer is no and you’re focusing on more conventional academic work. I take the theory of change here, as you say to be “make rigorous work more impactful”. But that seems to rely on getting institutional buy in from academia, which sounds quite uphill. An alternative path is “to make impactful (i.e., EA) work more rigorous”. I’d guess there’s already a large appetite for this in EA. How you see the tradeoffs here?
I expect that once there’s been quite a few unjournal reviews, that people will attempt to compare scores across projects. I.e., I can imagine a world in which a report / paper receives a 40⁄100 and people point out “This is below the 60⁄100 of the average article in the same area”. How useful do you expect such comparisons to be? Do you think there could / should be a way to control for the depth of the analysis?
I wonder if a positive step would be to raise the retirement age?
This sounds plausible. I wonder if people’s attitudes towards retirement is a huge affective forecasting error where they think it’ll be sublime, but it ends up isolating and boring (like school breaks were for me as a kid).
Anecdotally, children and grandchildren seem to form an increasing fraction of people’s social network as they age because they attrition much slower than friends or colleagues (assuming you’re not a terrible parent)
But I wonder if that attrition isn’t related to parenthood. I haven’t had kids yet but my friends seem to drop off the map socially as they become parents. It’s sort of concerning. Having children also seems pretty isolating to many living in environments that cater to nuclear families.
Surely there’s evidence for this question as it pertains to loneliness. I know that having grandchildren is clearly good for subjective wellbeing, but the evidence for the effects of parenthood, in general, are much more mixed/ambiguous.
I appreciate this post! Loneliness is something I think about often because it appears to be, alongside mental health issues, as one of the things that appears relatively worse for people’s subjective wellbeing than say, their income.
That being said, it was always unclear what can be done, and this review doesn’t seem to suggest there’s a frontrunner in terms of interventions.
I’m puzzled that so many interventions involve 1 on 1 interactions. This doesn’t seem scalable or in the spirit of well, decreasing loneliness.
Group interventions seem more promising but there appears to be less evidence.
I wonder if the reason why group-psychotherapy in some cases appears better than 1 on 1 therapy is because of an added loneliness reduction bonus.
I’d also be curious to hear what ideas there are for new interventions / RCTs.
Intergenerational cohabitation seems like a plausible way to solve two problems at once. Older people are lonelier and have more housing. Younger people don’t have much housing. Why not connect them? I’d be curious to see the results for an RCT of a matchmaking programme.
I feel like there are obvious intervention’s no one’s tested: try to connect lonely people to one another, perhaps in a group setting with a facilitator? How much does a website/ app like Meetup already do this?
I’d also be interested to know if there are any quasi-experiments that could be studied related to larger scale interventions. I.e., does the walkability of a city increase wellbeing through decreases in loneliness? What about more social clubs?
A question I’m curious about is what are the biggest barriers to lonely people going out and making friends on their own? Is it transportation? Cost? Unclear where to go? Church used to be the easy button, but many people aren’t religious anymore and we don’t have a clear substitute. Why isn’t this a problem that markets can solve?
What about digital interventions? Some people seem to be content with forming and maintaining relationships through a digital medium (e.g., online gaming).
I’d also really like to know how common loneliness is in low income countries, and how the barriers differ towards forming more positive social bonds.
I find nothing objectionable in that characterization. And if we only had these three studies to guide us then I’d concede that a discount of some size seems warranted. But we also have A. our priors. And B. some new evidence from Barker et al. Both of point me away from very small spillovers, but again I’m still very unsure. I think I’ll have clearer views once I’m done analyzing the Barker et al. results and have had someone, ideally Nathanial Barker, check my work.
[Edit: Michael edited to add: “It’s not clear any specific number away from 0 could be justified.”] Well not-zero certainly seems more justifiable than zero. Zero spillovers implies that emotional empathy doesn’t exist, which is an odd claim.