Thereâs an element of preaching to the choir in posting this here, and of course dietary choice seems much less important than choices around where to donate. But I still think this FAQ, which is really more of a Q, could be of interest to EAF users.
Preamble
Why did you write this FAQ?
I wrote this FAQ to explain why I think it is the case that animals raised for food suffer a lot, and why, as a result, people oughtnât to eat meat. Others have written similar things, but I wanted to explain my own reasons for not eating meat. Some people think eating meat is bad because it causes greenhouse gas emissions. Others avoid meat for health reasons. Personally, I would not eat meat even if it turned out that eating meat helped fight climate change.[1]
(That said, as Iâll discuss later, I also think actions other than going vegetarian or vegan can have even greater impact. For example, donating to effective animal charities often does more good, and eliminating factory-farmed eggs reduces more suffering than eliminating beef. I donât claim that vegetarianism is the best thing one can do for animals, only that it is very good compared to doing nothing.)
If Iâm right about the suffering of factory-farmed animalsâand suspend your judgment on that point for nowâthen what weâre doing to those animals is one of the worst moral catastrophes in history, comparable to the worst instances of slavery, war and genocide. If so, it is an ongoing moral catastrophe affecting victims that cannot advocate for themselves.
Generally speaking, whenever we risk making a serious moral mistake, we should think it through carefully and honestly, just like those involved in the Atlantic Slave trade or the Great Leap Forward (or other risky endeavours that had more positive outcomes) should have thought carefully and honestly about what they were doing.[2] But a lot of the arguments against vegetarianism that I see are weak, suggesting to me that most people have not thought carefully enough about eating meat. Even if one ultimately concludes that eating meat is fine, that decision should at least be grounded in solid evidence and reasoning.
Why should I read this if youâre just trying to persuade me?
Clearly Iâm not a neutral observer here. But Iâve made a lot of effort to let empirical facts and good-faith reasoning speak for themselves. And you stand to gain from reading this! The most obvious benefit is that you would be doing some of that necessary careful thinking I mentioned above. But also:
You may be curious to find out what I think
You may want to better understand why a vegetarian/âvegan friend or relative might have made that choice
You may want to find the part where you disagree with me
You may be one of those rare people who just enjoy challenging their beliefs
In many ways, the deck is stacked in favour of eating meat. When someone first questions the morality of eating meat, they face multiple mental and social obstacles. First, they must admit that their previous behaviour has been wrong, a difficult thing. Second, they have to either change their attitude towards eating meat to one that disapproves of their behaviour, or change their actual behaviour, harder things still. And third, they may fear stigma, disapproval or awkwardness from telling others they no longer eat meat. (That is the case, at least, in many social settings, though not all.) These factors create psychological pressure to avoid seriously considering ethical issues around meat consumption.[3] These considerations donât prove anything, but they are reasons to keep an open mind.
How is this FAQ organised?
The FAQ comprises ten sections:
A preamble (you are here)
The basic case for why I think eating meat is wrong
The natural and divine
The moral status of animals
Whether animals truly feel or experience things
Benefits humans can gain from eating meat
Benefits that animals can gain from being farmed
Whether an individualâs meat consumption truly causes animal death and suffering
Possible disadvantages of vegetarianism
Implications following from the earlier sections
Why Think Eating Meat Is Wrong?
Why do you think eating meat is wrong?
Hereâs the argument in the fewest possible words:
Every day, hundreds of millions of farmed animals are killed, the majority of whom are factory-farmed (Ritchie 2023). In the US alone, around 10B farm animals are killed each year, an estimated 99% of which are factory-farmed (Ritchie 2023).
The lives of factory-farmed animals are characterised by deprivation, pain, suffering and boredom. At minimum, raising an animal for meat involves killing the animal as soon as itâs grown to its full weight, which occurs when they are still very young compared to their natural life expectancy. Because these animals are very likely capable of feeling and perceiving pain, boredom and so on, their pain and suffering matters.
This state of affairs would hardly exist, or at least be greatly diminished, if it wasnât for people eating meat. Hence, it is wrong to eat meat.
Obviously many will dispute some of those claims. The first claim is empirical, while the second and third claims involve a combination of evidence and value judgments. The remainder of this FAQ will explore all three in more detail.
But first, let me expand a little on the staggering scale of factory farming. Each year, over 100B animals are killed for meat and other animal products (Ritchie 2023), about as many as the number of humans who have ever lived on Earth.[4] Humans eat lots of different animals, from cows and pigs to dogs and horses and fish and whales and insects, but let us focus on the most commonly eaten land animals: cows, pigs and chickens. In the US, 33M cows, 130M pigs and 9.4B chicken are killed annually. That is 10%, 38% and 2,800% of the US human population (340M), respectively. In the EU, according to my estimates, 24M cows, 290M pigs and 9.3B chicken are slaughtered for meat annually.[5] Most of these animals are raised in factory farms. In the US, 98% of pigs, 70% of cows, and 99.97% of chicken are factory-farmed (Ritchie 2023). The global number is likely lower, but still suggests a majority is factory-farmed; according to one estimate, about three quarters of global land livestock is factory-farmed. These numbers are fairly rough but the orders of magnitude are uncontroversial.
Ok, so why did you stop eating meat?
I stopped eating meat for the reasons I just outlined.
I ate meat for a little over 25 years, having grown up in a meat-eating household. I think I stopped in 2014 or 2015, so about a decade ago. But by then I had already for some time arrived at the conclusion that eating meat was wrong. In fact, I looked through my email history just now and learned that I wrote, on 24 March 2012: âIf I had any power of will I would be a vegetarian. But Iâm too lazy and I like meat.â
So at some point around or prior to 2012 I must have been persuaded that eating meat was wrong. I donât remember exactly what persuaded me, but I remember that it was the moral argument about animal welfare, not arguments around health or climate change, that persuaded me. I especially came to think that torturing animals in factory farms was bad and wrong. I did not overcome my laziness to become vegetarian until 2016 or so. In 2021, I became vegan.
Isnât âtortureâ a little extreme?
Iâm using the word âtortureâ according to the dictionary definition: to âinflict severe pain or suffering onâ or âcause great mental suffering or anxiety toâ someone.
Animals on industrial farms are routinely confined to highly restrictive spaces that prevent them from walking, turning around or extending their limbs. In 2008, the Pew Charitable Trustsâhardly an animal rights organisationâpublished a report on US industrial farm animal production. The report was chaired by a former governor of Kansas who had previously been a dairy farmer and it concluded: âAfter reviewing the literature, visiting production facilities, and listening to producers themselves, the Commission believes that the most intensive confinement systems, such as restrictive veal crates, hog gestation pens, restrictive farrowing crates, and battery cages for poultry, all prevent the animal from a normal range of movement and constitute inhumane treatment.â
These âmost intensive confinement systemsâ are extremely common, especially in the US. Sows and chicken spend many weeks immobilized in body-sized cages, but even short periods are distressing. As one Auschwitz survivor put it (describing a standing cell):
It was a terrible state, as I thought that it was over for me, everything seemed so indifferent and distant to me. I couldnât lie down, I couldnât squat, the best thing was to stand, stand for six days and six nights. [...] With your elbows you touch the walls on both sides, with your back you touch the wall behind you, with your knees the wall in front of you. [...] This is no punishment or pre-trial detention, it is torture, straightforward medieval torture. I had bloodshot eyes, was stupefied by the bad air, and just waited for the end.
Animals in factory farms are routinely mutilated. For example, when pigs are overcrowded and deprived of stimulation, they sometimes bite each otherâs tails. The standard solution to this problem is to cut off the pigâs tail when it is young (Sutherland and Tucker 2011). Male piglets are restrained and their testicles are cut out with a knife in order to avoid a bad smell (âboar taintâ) when cooked (De Briyne et al. 2016; von Borell et al. 2009). Chicken have parts of their beaks removed to prevent injury and cannibalisation (Kuenzel 2007). Calves have their horns cut off using clippers and hot irons (Gottardo et al. 2011).[6] All these things are routine in the meat industry, often done without anesthesia or even painkillers, and rarely carried out by trained veterinarians. The pain they induce is most likely excruciating.
I donât trust those accounts of animal abuses. Sure, maybe some factory farms are that bad, but in most of them, animals are probably treated humanely?
If you are skeptical that anyone would treat animals like that, consider this very simple explanation. The meat industryâs primary purpose is to generate shareholder value. Thereâs nothing wrong with that as far as it goes, but it means thereâs strong pressure on companies to generate meat as cost-effectively as possibleâto reduce costs and maximise throughput. However, there are very few laws regulating the conditions of animals on factory farmsâin most places, the meat industry is free to do almost as it wants, so long as it is considered a necessary part of meat production.[7] (In the EU, things are a bit better than elsewhere, with directives setting some minimum welfare standards and some countries banning some of the most unseemly practices.[8]) As a result, the default outcome is that animal welfare concerns take a backseat in favour of cost reduction and efficiency.
This plot from Mekonnen et al. (2019) shows how animals now produce far more food than in the 20th century. A chicken born today contains twice as much meat as one born in 1960. A dairy cow born today produces three times as much milk as one born in 1960. In a way, this is good, because it means fewer animals need to go through factory farms to produce a given amount of meat. But it also involves placing more stress on the animal in a highly optimised system, as they are selectively bred and managed to grow extremely fast and to ever greater weights, causing lameness and other health issues (Clark, Potter, and Harding 2006).
Adding to those problems, farmed animals are often handled roughly and not unfrequently subjected to outright abuse. Theyâre put in crowded, featureless environments depriving them of their natural behaviours. Their living spaces are unsanitary and disease-riddenâfor example, >500M chickens have been killed (âdepopulatedâ) to contain various avian influenza outbreaks between 2005 and 2024 (Al Awaidy, Asghar, and Zaraket 2024). They get injured and their injuries are often left untreated. Females are forcefully impregnated with rods. Piglets are weaned from their mothers at two to four weeks instead of the natural three to four months and dairy calves are separated within hours (compared to the natural weaning period of ten months) (Faccin et al. 2020; Lewis 2016). When transported to slaughterhouses, they are packed into crowded trucks and denied food and water for extended periods; according to one estimate, â20 million chickens, 330,000 pigs and 166,000 cattle are dead on arrival, or soon after, at abattoirs in the US every year [...] 800,000 pigs are calculated to be unable to walk on arrivalâ. And so on. Again, these are just the natural consequences of a system designed to maximise cost-effectiveness with minimal oversight. There would be nothing wrong with this if it were not the case that the products are living animals.
(Benjamin Hilton has written an excellent essay describing conditions in factory farms in more detail, and quite even-handedly. Less even-handedly, the documentary Dominion has a lot of factory farm footage.)
You canât just tally billions of animals like that and conclude they are more important than a smaller number of humans. Arenât you assuming utilitarianism?
I think it is wrong to eat meat under any reasonable moral framework. That includes utilitarianism, deontology, virtue ethics, care ethics and plain common sense. Putting aside the empirical questions for a moment, all I assume here is that it is good and important to promote the general welfare. That view is compatible with utilitarianism, deontology, virtue ethics, care ethics and any other reasonable moral theory I can think of. You can find arguments for and against eating meat by philosophers of just about any school.[9] Arguments against eating meat include Singer (1975) from utilitarianism, Regan (1983) and Korsgaard (2018) from deontology, Adams (1990) from feminist ethics and Scully (2002) from conservative Christian ethics. Even Roger Scruton, one of few philosophers who took up the position against animal rights, condemned factory farming: âSomeone who was indifferent to the sight of pigs confined in batteries, who did not feel some instinctive need to pull down these walls and barriers and let in light and air, would have lost sight of what it is to be a living animalâ (Scruton 1996).
Anyway, I mention the numbers because the numbers matter. Behind each number are many individual animals. When you see a number like â73,000,000,000 chickens slaughtered per yearâ, it is only a number. But at the risk of stating the obvious, those are 73,000,000,000 individual chickens, each with its own mind and personality. Just like saving two human lives is better than saving one human life, if killing one animal is bad, then killing 73B animals is far worse. For a typical person in the West, a decade of vegetarianism could save something like 210-280 chickens, 4-6 pigs, 0.5-1 cows and many other farmed (and wild caught) animals.[10]
How can you say eating meat is wrong according to common sense? Nearly everyone eats meat. Like, for many thousands of years the proportion of humans that have abstained from meat must have been well below 10%. Shouldnât we expect most people to be vegetarian if eating meat were truly so terrible?
I donât think most people have made a serious attempt at figuring out whether it is good or permissible to eat meat. Many vegetarians and vegans probably have, since most of them grew up as meat eaters, and they must have switched for some reason. But the majority of people grow up as and remain omnivores and probably never seriously consider whether eating meat is permissibleâas in, they may vaguely think about it once in a while, but donât sit down and run through the arguments the way we are doing here. (Very few omnivores grew up as vegetarians or vegans, so the reverse doesnât apply.)
People often unconsciously process information in a way that supports their pre-existing preferences or self-interestâthis is called motivated reasoning and is a widespread finding in psychology (Epley and Gilovich 2016). Since most people grow up eating meat, the way they seek evidence and evaluate arguments will tend to favour eating meat. The reverse is true of vegetarians and vegans, by the way, but most vegetarians and vegans have also at some point been on the other side. We canât assume that just because most people do a thing, it is morally justifiable. Slavery is not morally justifiable and was widespread for millennia of human history. Just as societies can cling to false empirical beliefs for centuries in the face of contrary evidence (e.g. heliocentrism), they can also persist in moral error for centuries.
God and Nature
Animals kill animals all the time. Itâs the natural state of things. The wolf kills the deer, the owl kills the field mouse and the lynx kills the hare. So why shouldnât the human kill the cow, the pig and the chicken?
If children constantly bully each other, does that make it fine to bully children? Itâs true that animals murder, rape, steal and destroy their offspring. But that does not automatically mean we are free to do all those things to the animals. (And itâs worth noting that many commonly farmed animals, like cows, pigs and chicken tend not to kill and eat each other.) Animals do terrible things to each other because they cannot do otherwise. They just act instinctively. They lack the cognitive abilities needed to make moral judgments. We, on the other hand, do have those abilities and can act morally. And when we donât, we are blameworthy.
I think itâs important not to mistake moral agency from moral standing. Moral standing is the right to have oneâs interests factored into othersâ moral choices, whereas moral agency is the ability to make moral choices. My claim, summarised in the table below, is that animals have moral standing, but not moral agency. (More on the moral status of animals later.)
Thing Moral standing Moral agency
Human Yes Yes
Pig Yes No
Rock No[11] No
Didnât God give humans dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth, and over every creeping thing that creepeth upon the earth?
Iâm not religious, but from what I can tell, the Bible does not provide clear moral guidance when it comes to animals and factory farming, and so Christians canât rely solely on scripture for these ethical decisionsâthey need to engage in independent moral reasoning. The âdominionâ passage (Genesis 1:26) is probably the most important and action-guiding one. I havenât read Scully (2002) but I know itâs written by a conservative and I gather it argues we should interpret the dominion passage as a call to stewardship, not a carte blanche to do whatever we want with animals. When humans are called on to rule over humans, that doesnât normally include a right to torture them.
It is true that various Biblical passages condone or depict meat eating, animal sacrifice and so on. For example, after the Flood, God gave Noah explicit permission to eat meat (Genesis 9:3): âEverything that lives and moves about will be food for you. Just as I gave you the green plants, I now give you everything.â I suppose Adam and Eve were vegan initially, and Daniel and his companions chose a vegetarian diet for a while (Daniel 1:8-16), but as far as I know there are no ethical vegetarians in the Bible. But the Bible seems to condone and depict many practices that we now reject, like slavery, polygamy and capital punishment for minor offenses. It was written (or inspired) at a time that was extremely different from today, so we canât naively use it as a direct guide for contemporary moral issues like factory farming, especially since factory farms didnât even exist back then.
Whatâs more, some Biblical passages offer guidance that seems incompatible with modern factory farming. For example, Proverbs 12:10 says âthe righteous care for the needs of their animalsâ. Exodus 20:10 says that, on the Sabbath, âyou shall not do any work, neither you, nor your son or daughter, nor your male or female servant, nor your animalsâ. In Godâs covenant with Noah after the Flood (Genesis 9:9-10), He includes âthe birds, the livestock and all the wild animals ⊠every living creature on earthâ.
Would you also not eat lab-grown meat? Thatâs meat, tooâat least according to you vegetarians and vegans. And what about roadkillâwould you say itâs fine to eat that?
What matters to me are the experiences that animals live through, and the practices causing those experiences. I keep the rule âdonât eat meatâ because I find it simpler and easier to keep a simple rule, but I donât think itâs necessarily always wrong to eat meat. Eating roadkill, eating lab-grown meat and eating meat when it is necessary for survival, all seem acceptable to me. Iâm only saying that, for most people, and in most situations, the benefits of eating meat (that came from animals) are greatly outweighed by the harm it involves.
The Moral Status of Animals
How can we know that animals matter morally at all?
There is no certainty in ethics, but I think most ways we can justify caring about other humansâ welfare also end up justifying caring about many species of animal (if perhaps to a lesser degree). In particular, most would agree that pain and suffering are intrinsically bad, and it seems irrelevant whether the pain or suffering is happening to a human or some other animal, so long as it is being consciously experienced.
I will discuss animal sentience (the capacity to perceive and feel) later, but for now, let me point out that Iâm not arguing a minority position hereâthere is widespread agreement that animals matter morally. Most countries have laws against animal cruelty, and many Western countries formally recognise non-human animal sentience.[12] In fact, nearly everyone acts as if at least some animals do matter morallyâthey just donât apply the belief consistently. The vast majority of peopleâat least in modern societies[13] -- consider it morally wrong to, say, douse cats in acid or punch dogs. Why would those actions be morally wrong if animals donât matter?
Kant argued that animal abuse is wrong only because it damages our own moral character. Maybe that is why we have those laws and reactions against animal abuse, and not because of the animals themselves?
I donât think so. When we oppose animal cruelty, we typically feel we do it because animals deserve protection for their own sake, not because being kind to animals makes us better people. My moral intuition, at least, tells me that an animalâs pain matters directly, even if it does not affect human character. That is one common critique against Kantâs argument. Another critique, which I came across in Korsgaard (2018), argues that Kantâs reasoning is âalmost incoherentâ. If we only care about animals because it ultimately helps us treat humans better, then we do not really care about the animals themselvesâwe are only using them as tools for our own moral development. But that does not seem like an attitude Kant would want us to cultivate, since he also argued strongly that we should not treat moral patients (humans, in his view) as mere means.
I think there is some truth in Kantâs reasoning: it is good for us to take a benevolent attitude towards sentient beings, because that makes it more likely that we make good moral decisions. If we acknowledge that animals can suffer and that this suffering matters enough to create indirect duties, weâve already implicitly granted them some form of moral status that canât be coherently reduced to mere instrumental value for human character development. That is, why would torturing an animal be damaging to our moral character? The simplest explanation is: because torturing an animal is morally wrong. (For a more comprehensive summary and critique of Kantâs reasoning on this question, see Korsgaard (2018).)
But even if Kant is right and animal abuse is wrong only indirectly due to its effect on us humans, that would still be a problem for factory farming. Because factory farming is a form of animal abuse and it is nothing if not human-caused.
Are you sure youâre not just falling for anthropomorphic bias? How do you know your compassion for animals isnât a misfiring of caregiving instincts we have for infants?
I agree that anthropomorphism is a real phenomenon that can distort our intuitions on these questions. That is why I put a lot of weight on observable markers like animalsâ brain structure, their behaviour and our shared evolutionary history, more on which later. And as a result, I think there is good reason to also care about animals that are dissimilar to humans, like cephalopods, fishes and crustaceans, even though these are likely less sentient than cows, pigs and chickens.
Still, there is probably some accidental truth to anthropomorphism. Sentience probably exists on a spectrum, as a result of its having evolved gradually over millions of years.[14] Since humans appear to possess the highest degree of sentience, it makes sense that our closest evolutionary relatives would be more sentient than distant ones. These closer relatives also tend to share more physical and behavioral traits with us.
Animals are much less intelligent than humans. Isnât that a reason to treat them differently from humans?
I do not have a good answer to this question, because I never understood why intelligence would matter when determining the moral status of animals, except as a correlate of factors that do matter, e.g. the capacity to experience pain. We certainly donât consider intelligence relevant when deciding the moral status of humans; ignoring any second-order effects, it is equally bad to inflict pain on a human with an IQ of 110 as it is on someone with an IQ of 90. Some humans are severely intellectually disabledâenough to be less intelligent (for any reasonable definition of âintelligenceâ) than some animalsâand yet their suffering matters too.
It is possible that greater intelligence unlocks some types of higher-complexity suffering. For example, Robert Oppenheimer probably suffered from the moral dilemma he faced in the development of the atomic bomb. That exact flavour of suffering is probably not available to chickens. (Or perhaps it is, and it is only the cause of the suffering that is unavailable to chickens.) But you could also imagine intelligence helping to alleviate suffering, for example, by allowing sophisticated mental coping strategies. I donât know what the net effect is. Either way, that still leaves the other animals with plenty of important varieties of suffering that are unlikely to require substantial intelligence, e.g. physical pain.
Okay, but severely intellectually disabled people are still members of the category of humans, doesnât that count for something?
That sounds arbitrary to me. What is it that makes âbeing humanâ morally relevant? Why draw the circle around âhumanâ and not around âEuropeanâ or âthose who dream in black and whiteâ or âmammalâ for that matter? Suppose tomorrow scientists discovered a group of Neanderthals or Denisovans living in caves undergroundâcan we then do whatever we want to them because they are not members of H. sapiens, despite their possessing all the traits we associate with personhood? Species membership just doesnât seem like a morally relevant characteristic, especially compared to things like âcapacity to sufferâ and âhaving preferencesâ, where the relationship to morality is obvious.[15]
Animal Sentience and Consciousness
How can we possibly know that animals feel pain?
I am not saying that we can know animals feel pain. There is no certainty in sentience. How can you know other humans feel pain? They can tell you they feel pain, but thereâs always some chance theyâre lying or mistakenâyou have no access to their internal experience. You can only know that you feel pain and observe that other humans are similar to you in relevant ways.
Because we cannot know for sure whether the other animals can feel pain, we have to make decisions under uncertainty. So we need to find out how probable it is that animals feel pain (and so on), and then decide whether or not to eat meat with that probability in mind. Given how terrible conditions are in factory farms, and given that eating meat necessitates killing animals, we ought to avoid eating meat even if itâs only somewhat likely that those animals feel pain.
Okay, then how can we be sure itâs somewhat likely that animals feel pain?
Letâs start with a shared premise:
It is almost certain that humans typically can feel pain.
Humansâ ability to feel pain derives from certain structures in the brain and body.
Those structures evolved through natural selection, presumably because pain sensing conferred survival and reproductive advantages.
Humans and other animals have a long shared evolutionary history resulting in many common neurological features. For example, many animals have neural pathways (e.g. pain receptors) similar to ours that detect and respond to potentially damaging stimuli (Smith and Lewin 2009). There are also common brain regions (e.g. the amygdala and the anterior cingulate cortex) that show similar activation patterns in humans and other mammals when exposed to adverse stimuli (Hayes and Northoff 2011, 2012).
These similarities are borne out by behavioural studies (and common experience) showing that animals typically go to great lengths to avoid harmful stimuli, as youâd expect if they found pain unpleasant (Sneddon et al. 2014). For example, in one experiment, rats learned to push bedding in front of them as a protective shield when approaching shocking electrodes (Pinel, Mana, and Ward 1989). Animalsâ responses to harmful stimuli also change if you give them painkillers like opioids or NSAIDs (Fischer 2022). That is not just the result of painkillers reducing overall activityâfor example, when given the option to self-medicate, lame chickens will actively take more painkillers than healthy chickens (Whittaker and Howarth 2014; Danbury et al. 2000).
Maybe animals have pain responses without really being aware or conscious of pain?
Maybe. Sometimes when I am in pain for a longer period of time, the pain can fade from awareness as I get distracted by other things. But when my attention is called to the pain, I become aware of it again. A pain receptor firing (nociception) and triggering motor responses is different from the raw feel of painâthe actual sensation that makes us want it to stop. So it seems fair to ask whether animals are in that state of unawareness constantly, only reflexively responding to negative stimuli?
I think the best approach for answering this question is, again, to look at evolutionary, neurological and behavioural parallels with humans. The behavioural evidence in particular seems hard to reconcile with the âunawareness of painâ view. For example, some animals demonstrate pain-related behaviours well after the initial nociceptive response would have faded. As pet owners know, animals can learn to avoid areas where they encounter pain (Rushen and Congdon 1986; Dunlop, Millsopp, and Laming 2006; Crook 2021). In other experiments, rats and even fruit flies learned to seek out stimuli experienced right after getting shocked, probably because these stimuli meant âthe shock is now overâ (Gerber et al. 2014). And as mentioned previously, some animals learn to self-medicate when in pain. In my estimate, these behaviors suggest pain awareness reaches higher-level cognitive processing and influences decision-making, rather than just triggering reflexive responses. (For more on animal sentience, again, see the essay by Benjamin Hilton.)
While the behavioural and neurological evidence isnât as robust as it is for pain, I think other important aspects of well-being, like pleasure, agency, social connection and feelings of awe, are probably also present in many animals. My favourite example is an experiment where octopuses spent more time, and engaged in more physical contact, with other octopuses after being given MDMA (ecstasy) (Edsinger and Dölen 2018). I only focus on pain because pain, or rather the absence of pain, seems extremely important to well-beingâprobably more important than all those other aspects. When someone is in severe pain, almost nothing else matters except making the pain stop. The same is not true for most other negative experiences, or the absence of positive experiences.
How can we be sure that plants donât feel pain, too?
It is true that some plants respond to harmful stimuli and stress in some rudimentary sense. But plants almost certainly do not experience pain or suffering, as they lack nervous systems and brains. They are also far more distant from us evolutionarily than farmed animals: humans and cows/âpigs diverged nearly 100M years ago, humans and chickens diverged around 300M years ago and humans and fish around 390M years ago, but humans and plants diverged around 1.5B years ago.
Do you eat fish? Fish donât feel pain.
I used to eat fish and, when I was a child, would occasionally go fishing with my uncles and cousins. I was not a successful fisher but I remember distinctly hooks being pulled out of piscine cheeks and our vigorously bludgeoning pike and perch to death with our boots. I also distinctly remember believing that fish donât feel pain.
It has now been over a decade since I last ate fish and I now think itâs very likely that fish do in fact feel pain, though the case is weaker than for birds and mammals (Brown 2015; Lambert et al. 2022). Even if fish are less sentient than mammals, eating fish might cause more total suffering because you need to kill many more individual fish to get the same amount of meat. For example, replacing one cow with thousands of sardines or dozens of salmon could mean causing more total harm, even if each individual fish has less capacity for suffering. Comparing moral status across species is incredibly complex and difficult but also unavoidable if we want to make moral decisions. We are constantly making choices that (explicitly or implicitly) compare the moral worth of different species.
How about bivalves like clams, mussels, oystersâdo you eat those?
I donât, but that is mostly because they are not very appealing to me. Since bivalves lack brains and have only rudimentary nervous systems, it is probably fine to eat them, and I know of several animal advocates who do.[16]
Benefits to Humans from Eating Meat
Donât you find meat tasty?
I donât know. I certainly used to, though now I find the idea of eating meat off-putting. Either way, I grant that many people do derive substantial pleasure from eating meat and that this matters.
How much does it matter? I think preventing torture is clearly more important than having access to better-tasting food. We donât generally accept âbut I enjoy itâ as a justification for causing serious harm. Say you are willing to pay $X to upgrade a vegetarian meal to a pork-based meal. A modern pig yields enough meat for about 400 meals and lives for about six months until itâs slaughtered, meaning each meal corresponds to about 14 hours of pig-life in a factory farm. (Or if you do not eat pork, take chicken. A meal of chicken would mean an entire week in a factory farm, because chickens are so small.) Now how much would you pay to avoid being confined to a factory farm for 14 hours? How much money would you need to be paid to let your dog, or a friendâs dog, be treated like a factory-farmed animal for 14 hours?[17] Youâd probably pay more than $X to avoid the torture.
Donât you need to eat meat to feel healthy and energetic? Humans did evolve as omnivores. Meat provides calories and nutrients that benefit us.
It is true that we are omnivores who have essentially always had meat as part of our diets. It could have been the case that it was necessary for us to eat meat to be healthy. But the health effects of vegetarianism have been fairly extensively studied, and I think we can be confident that it is possible to eat a healthy vegetarian diet. There is no nutrient necessary for human health that can only be found in meat.
I previously reviewed evidence around the health effects of veganism, concluding that âvegan diets are healthier than common Western diets, and perhaps also somewhat healthier than good Western and non-Western omnivore diets [if] the vegan gets all the nutrients that they needâ. It is, of course, essential that vegans do get the nutrients they need, by supplementing some nutrients. But vegetarianism is far less restrictive than veganism, so supplementing often isnât necessary for vegetarians. For example, vitamin B12, which vegans must supplement, is available in dairy. That said, the health effects of vegetarianism and veganism is one of the areas in this FAQ that I am less sure about. Iâm reasonably confident that vegetarianism especially is not significantly detrimental to peopleâs health the way, say, drinking alcohol is. But it seems hard to rule out minor disadvantages (or advantages) given the current evidence base. It is probably a good idea to take a nutrition/âvitamin deficiency test, regardless of your diet.
Can you get enough protein without meat?
Meat products do typically have more protein per calorie than plant-based products. But legumes like beans, lentils, peas and chickpeas are delicious, cheap and full of protein too. Nuts, seeds and whole grains (oat, barley, quinoa, brown rice, whole wheat) are also useful. Tofu and tempeh have about as much protein per calorie as eggs, salmon and beef. Depending on where one lives, there are also plant-based meats that improve in quality and variety every year. And, if you must, dairy products like milk and cheese are protein-rich. The Mediterranean diet is famously good and involves relatively little meat but lots of nuts, legumes and whole grains.
If you need a lot of protein, for example, because you are an athlete or go to the gym, there are plant-based protein bars and powder. I am neither an athlete nor a gym rat, but I am given to understand there are several successful vegan and vegetarian athletes and bodybuilders. For example, Carl Lewis, Lewis Hamilton and Venus Williams were all vegan during most of their careers.
But meat eating is a continuation of a long-standing cultural practice.
Here are some other long-standing cultural practices: chattel slavery, foot binding, public executions and female genital mutilation. A practice being traditional does not automatically mean we should continue it. It could mean we should be careful about stopping it, since it may have evolved to serve a useful function. Being careful about stopping eating meat means thinking through arguments like those presented in this FAQ.
We tend to think the way things happen to be, is the way things ought to be. For example, in discussions of efforts to cure aging and prevent death, people sometimes argue that doing so is wrong because aging and death is what grants life meaning. Those arguments are probably often the result of status quo bias. If the world were different and no one aged past thirty, and we could choose when to die, no sane person would ever advocate arbitrarily and compulsorily ending peopleâs lives at a hundred, in order to make those lives more meaningful (Bostrom and Ord 2006). You can apply the same reversal test to meat eating by imagining a society where universal vegetarianism is the default and the moral burden of proof falls on meat eaters.
Arenât there animals that are raised with high standards, and that lead happy lives?
There surely are farm animals out there living happy lives. Those happy animals are almost certainly not living in factory farms, though, and, as mentioned, most animals raised for food are raised in factory farms. In the US, seven in ten cows, 49 in 50 pigs, and 3,332 in 3,333 chickens are raised in factory farms; the European numbers are likely similar. So I would need to actively seek out humane meat. If conditions in factory farms are as bad as I think they are, I would want to be very sure that the meat in fact did not come from a factory farm. Not only that, I would also want further evidence that the animal was treated well, since not all non-factory-farmed animals are raised humanely.
In practice, that seems like a tall order. If I buy meat in a supermarket, I can look for animal welfare labels, but food labels can be misleadingâfor example, ânaturalâ in the US only means no artificial ingredients, not that animals had outdoor access, as many think (Spain et al. 2018). Other labels are not regulated, or regulated but not verified. Knowing whether meat is humane is even more difficult if I am eating at a restaurant, in an airplane, while traveling abroad or at a friendâs home. And researching different suppliers and standards costs time and effort.
Still, perhaps you could find some meat that you are highly confident is humane, and you could eat that meat while being vegetarian otherwise. Maybe wild game from hunting could count, for example.
Yes, perhaps I could. It is, of course, better to eat animals that were raised with high welfare standards than to eat those that were not, all else equal. There are three reasons why I still do not eat meat:
Even if an animal lives a happy life, someone still has to kill it for me to eat it. Everyone agrees that itâs wrong to kill a human, even when he or she is not made to suffer.[18] If animals also matter morally, it seems similarly wrong to kill an animal.[19]
Strict vegetarianism (or in my case, veganism) offers useful signaling advantages. Vegetarianism is a clear, binary choice that others can easily verify and understand. That creates a clear coordination point for building social norms against factory farming. By contrast, humane meat eating is fuzzyâit is hard to agree on what counts as humane and hard to verify that someone eats humane meat.
It seems better to me to have the clear boundary that vegetarianism (or veganism, or any other well-defined rule) provides. Once you start making exceptions, I think it often leads to a gradual slide back to regular eating habits, because thereâs no stable middle ground. Without a clear boundary, I think people tend to make more and more exceptions until their diet is mostly back to normal, and the original moral motivation becomes diluted. I think it is easier to stick to absolute rules, as they make lapses more obvious and harder to excuse, but even so, it is of course important to adopt pragmatic and achievable rules.
If I were to eat some amount of meat selectively, I would first of all make sure to eat beef rather than pork or chicken. That is because, to get the same amount of meat as I could get for one cow, I would need to eat three or four pigs, or nearly two hundred chickens. Also, pigs and chickens typically face harsher conditions than cows.
Benefits to Animals from Eating Meat
If everyone were to stop using animal products, cows, pigs and chickens would go extinct. Doesnât that seem bad for them?
I find it very unlikely that they would go completely extinct. Just like horses and carrier pigeons, animals that lose their practical use to humans donât go extinct, they survive as pets or in sanctuaries, just in smaller numbers.[20]
All right, but there would be far fewer cows, pigs and chickens. Donât most cows, pigs and chickens owe their existence to us meat eaters?
I am not sure I know what it means for a life to be âworth livingâ, but if the lives of factory-farmed cows, pigs and chickens were worth living, on the whole, despite being full of suffering, you could argue that eating their meat is good, as it creates more cows, pigs and chickens with lives worth living. Scruton (1996) makes this argument, though while criticising factory farming in particular. But I donât think the argument is sound. If a person who kept humans in captivity, who bred them for his or her own pleasure and who subjected them to a litany of abuses, justified his or her conduct by pointing out that the captives would not exist if it were not for him or her, and that the captivesâ lives are, despite the abuses, nonetheless worth living, you would take that for a very weak justification. Thatâs a specific instance of what we could call the Human Substitution Test, which I think is relevant because it helps us focus on the fundamental ethical principles of how we should treat morally relevant beings.
Either way, given the conditions these animals endure, it is unclear to me whether their lives are, in fact, worth living. I would guess they are probably not. It seems likely that these animals have far more negative than positive experiences over the course of their lives. They have little ability to pursue goals or flourish in any way. They are also denied the kinds of social lives that are natural to them.
Donât farmed animals, in some sense, have better lives than wild animals? Farmed animals receive shelter, food, protection from predators and, at least sometimes, veterinary care. Wild animals face brutal natural threats like starvation, disease and predation.
The question is not, should we replace farmed animals with wild animals? It is, how many farmed animals should we have and how should we treat them? The protections we offer farmed animals donât justify torture. Psychiatric hospitals used to give their patients food, shelter and basic medical care while putting them in straitjackets, isolating them in padded cells, controlling every aspect of their lives, from daily routines to outside contact, and subjecting them to forced sterilisation, lobotomies, electroconvulsive therapy without anesthesia, medical experiments and more.
Why Think Meat Consumption Is Wrong?
When I buy meat in the supermarket, the animal is already dead. If I instead choose not to buy that piece of meat, it wouldnât magically cause the animal to revive. So how can you say eating meat is bad for that animal?
It is true that buying the meat is not bad for that animal exactly. But buying or not buying the meat affects future demand and therefore future animals. As a first approximation, if everyone stopped buying meat, there would be no meat industry, and if everyone started buying twice as much, the meat industry would grow to keep up with the growing demand. So it seems reasonable to think the meat industry would shrink as a result of reduced demand.[21]
It also seems to me that, if itâs wrong to directly harm someone, itâs usually also wrong to pay others to do the harm. Huemer (2019): âFor instance, murder is wrong; so itâs also wrong to hire an assassin. If you hire an assassin to kill someone, you canât say that youâre not to blame just because you didnât pull the trigger yourself.â
Donât you think individual consumer choices have a negligible impact on large-scale meat demand and purchasing decisions made by supermarkets? Supermarkets purchase more meat than they sell, i.e., they have a buffer. If I stop buying meat, my local supermarket is extremely unlikely to reduce their order sizes.
If that were true, even a gradual mass movement of people stopping buying meat one by one would never affect production, which is absurd. An individual omitted purchase may often not have any effect. But each omitted purchase would have some chance of making the supermarket determine it is ordering too much meat. When it does, it will order substantially less meat. The same goes for each step of the supply chain. So on average, stopping to buy meat should reduce meat production.
Wouldnât reducing my meat consumption temporarily lower meat prices, leading other customers to purchase more meat?
When demand for meat drops, prices wonât perfectly adjust to maintain production levels. Instead, because meat prices are relatively inelastic (resistant to change), some producers will be forced out of business rather than all producers simply lowering their prices (Gallet 2010, 2012). That would reduce supply and increase prices. While remaining producers might try to cut costs through efficiency measures that could harm animals, the overall effect would still likely reduce factory farming and animal suffering.
Richard Yetter-Chappell argues roughly that (1) eating meat is unjustified, but a relatively minor mistake in the scheme of things, (2) itâs fine and extremely normal to make decisions that are less than perfectly justified and (3) other behavioural changes should be higher priorities, for example, helping animals by donating to effective animal welfare charities. What do you make of that argument?
I basically agree that becoming vegetarian is less impactful than donating to effective animal charities. Not because going vegetarian is ineffective, but because there are enormous opportunities to help animals through donations. There is a lot of uncertainty around these estimates, but it seems, for example, that for just one dollar donated to corporate campaigns for better chicken welfare, you can substantially improve 7-100 years of chicken life.[22] Even if the real impact is at the low end of that range, that is still a very cost-effective way of reducing animal suffering. For comparison, the average American would save about 28 chickens per year by stopping eating them and, with broiler chicken living 47 days on average, that means 3.6 years of chicken life.[23]
If you can only do one thing to help animals, in my view, donating to effective animal charities is more impactful than being vegetarian. But if you can do both, it seems better to do both. I recognise that for some people, going vegetarian would make it harder to donate, but I still think itâs worth giving vegetarianism a proper try. Personally, I have not noticed the two trading off against each other.
Isnât it wrong to focus on individual consumption? Shouldnât we focus on getting laws passed and so on instead?
Why not both? I think for most people the best way to help get laws passed is to donate to effective charities working in policy and advocacy. So in a way this question is very similar to the issue of dietary change versus donating discussed above.
Disadvantages of Vegetarianism
Animals are harmed in plant production too. For example, field mice and other small animals are sometimes caught in crop harvesters, and then there are pesticides.
Yes, small animals are killed in plant agricultural production. There seems to be an enormous amount of uncertainty around how many are killed (Fischer and Lamey 2018). But Iâm not sure it matters, because cows, pigs and chickens eat plants, too. While cattleâespecially beef cattleâget a large portion of food grazing, where crop harvesters are not a problem but pesticides are still used, every calorie of beef produced requires 50 plant calories eaten. Factory-farmed pig (1 cal out = 11 cal in) and chicken (1 cal out = 8 cal in) feed comes exclusively from plant agriculture, mostly cereals and soybean (Alexander et al. 2016; Sporchia, Kebreab, and Caro 2021; Govoni et al. 2021). Alexander et al. (2016) estimates that the Indian diet needs 25% of the land the US diet needs to produce the same amount of calories, mainly because itâs more vegetarian (getting 9% of energy from animal products, versus 30% for the US). The best (read: least worst) dietary impact estimate I could find has fruits, grains and vegetables killing 1-2 orders of magnitude fewer animals per calorie than meat:
As that graph shows, vegetarian diets are not free from harm. In particular, it seems really valuable to exclude eggs, probably more so than excluding beef. I am not making the claim that vegetarianism is the best thing ever one can do to help animals. For example, as mentioned, donating to effective charities seems to be more impactful than adopting vegetarianism. I am only saying that adopting vegetarianism seems much better than doing nothing.
How do you manage the higher (monetary) cost of a plant-based diet?
There are many vegetarian and vegan diets, some of which are as or more expensive than eating meat, others being cheaper. Legumes, grains and many vegetables are dirt cheap compared to meat. Some plant-based meats are more expensive than actual meat, probably because the meat industry benefits from economies of scale, decades of efficiency improvements and enormous state subsidies. (Western governments spend huge amounts of taxpayer money to support the meat industryâabout a third of the EUâs entire budget and tens of billions in the US support meat production, in both cases far outstripping subsidies for fruit and vegetable production.) But other plant-based meats are affordable, and switching protein intake to legumes and whole grains is great economically. There is a reason why people in very poor countries eat very little meat.
Isnât being vegetarian really inconvenient? It seems to make it much harder to find good restaurants, to eat out when traveling (especially in rural areas) and it also means your friends and family will have to accommodate you.
It depends a lot on where you live. I live in urban Northern Europe where it is very easy and everyone is very understanding. In rural Iowa it would be harder. But Iâd still try to be vegan or at least vegetarian even if it was really inconvenient. I would not eat humans just because it was convenient, so I also wonât eat animals. The hardest bit is changing to the new diet, but sticking to it gets easier over time as you adapt and it becomes your new normal, assuming you donât develop significant health problems.
Donât all your arguments imply that everyone should be vegan too? Thatâs even more inconvenient.
It is better to take smaller, achievable steps towards ethical goals than to do nothing because it is impossible to be perfect. I think most people should be vegan, or mostly vegan, if they are able. It seems especially valuable to avoid eggs and dairy from factory farms. But nobodyâs perfect and you do what you can. Making partial progress, like going vegetarian instead of fully vegan, or donating smaller amounts to effective animal charities instead of larger, is still valuable and worthwhile.
Implications
Do you want to ban eating meat?
No, I think a ban now would be wildly unpopular and unsustainable. I would like for norms to change to make eating meat less accepted, and vegetarianism and veganism more normal. I would also like to improve the welfare of factory-farmed animals. Maybe in the future, if and when public attitudes have shifted enough, a meat ban could become viable, but that is distant now. For now, there are many other good policies that governments could adopt, like banning battery cages and gestation crates and investing in alternative protein research.
Do you agree that vegetarians, and especially vegans, are preachy?
Yeah, occasionally. But that does not mean they are wrong. Donât do the wrong thing just because the people advocating for the right thing are annoying.
But also, I think the preachinessâto the extent that itâs thereâis fairly understandable and even defensible. If factory farming really is morally comparable to slavery in its severity, then people today who ignore or dismiss the issue are acting similarly to those in the American 1840s who casually accepted slavery as normal. How would you feel if everyone around you went on owning slaves, talking about slave-owning as something normal and fine and dismissing those pesky abolitionists for being judgy? You would probably be really, really tempted to suggest that perhaps they are in the wrong.
Do you think youâre morally superior to those who eat meat?
Like many others, I used to eat meat without questioning it. Now, I recognize it as wrong, and those who consume meat are engaging in that wrong, while I donât. If we can compare peopleâs morality, surely this counts in my favor in this particular area. Others are more virtuous than I am in other respects. So although I think eating meat is generally wrong, I donât think omnivores are generally evil. Iâve never met anyone without some moral failing.
That said, we should always strive to be better. When we eat meat we have, in my view, a great opportunity to reduce suffering in the world by changing our habits. If we realize weâve been doing something wrong, the right response is neither to rationalize it as being acceptable nor to despair that change is impossible. Rather, we should acknowledge the issue and recognize that each small improvement makes a difference.
Iâd like to stop eating meat but it seems pretty hard. I donât think I have the willpower.
The willpower needed to adopt vegetarianism varies tremendously from person to person. For me, though it took time, it was not that difficult, but I know that for some other people, it is. If you want to become vegetarian, you could start gradually by cutting out some products (like chicken and, ideally, eggs), or adopting the diet at home only, or only while eating out. You donât want to make the decision to eat vegetarian every time you sit down to eat. You want to make it once. So come up with a rule that works for you and stick to it. After a while, one improves at cooking plant-based dishes, discovers new vegetarian foods and (if one lives in the right place) finds good vegetarian-friendly restaurants and cafes, and it all becomes much easier.
But also, maybe ask yourself whether you really canât, or if you just think you canât. Lots of people have managed to go vegetarianâdo you think theyâre all superhumans with iron willpower? Huemer (2019) has a nice example: If you went vegetarian tomorrow, and had to pay $100 each time you ate meat, how often would you do it? If the answer is ânever or at least very rarelyâ, the urge to eat meat is probably not overpowering. Soon enough you will have internalized the âitâs bad to eat meatâ norm, and it will just seem normal and proper to you to not eat meat, and eating meat will seem strange and wrong.
Iâd like to stop eating meat but I canât for some other reason.
Here is an incomplete list of things you can try instead:
Offset your meat consumption by donating to effective animal charities. As I mentioned above, donating seems even more impactful than reducing oneâs animal product consumption.
Cut out chicken, pork and/âor eggs, in favour of beef or plant-based meats.
Reduce your meat consumption, for example by designating one or more days in the week when you always eat vegetarian.
Iâm still not convinced eating meat is wrong.
That is okay; Iâm glad you stuck with me to the end.
References
Adams, Carol J. 1990. âThe Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-Vegetarian Critical Theory.â
Al Awaidy, Salah T, Rana Jawad Asghar, and Hassan Zaraket. 2024. âHow Concerned Should We Be About the Recent Avian Influenza Outbreaks?â Oman Medical Journal 39 (2): e604.
Alexander, Peter, Calum Brown, Almut Arneth, John Finnigan, and Mark DA Rounsevell. 2016. âHuman Appropriation of Land for Food: The Role of Diet.â Global Environmental Change 41: 88--98.
Borell, Eberhard von, J Baumgartner, M Giersing, N JĂ€ggin, Armelle Prunier, FAM Tuyttens, and SA Edwards. 2009. âAnimal Welfare Implications of Surgical Castration and Its Alternatives in Pigs.â Animal 3 (11): 1488--96.
Bostrom, Nick, and Toby Ord. 2006. âThe Reversal Test: Eliminating Status Quo Bias in Applied Ethics.â Ethics 116 (4): 656--79. https://ââdoi.org/ââ10.1086/ââ505233
Brown, Culum. 2015. âFish Intelligence, Sentience and Ethics.â Animal Cognition 18 (1): 1--17.
Clark, JA MacArthur, Martin Potter, and E Harding. 2006. âThe Welfare Implications of Animal Breeding and Breeding Technologies in Commercial Agriculture.â Livestock Science 103 (3): 270--81.
Crook, Robyn J. 2021. âBehavioral and Neurophysiological Evidence Suggests Affective Pain Experience in Octopus.â Iscience 24 (3).
Danbury, TC, CA Weeks, AE Waterman-Pearson, SC Kestin, and JP Chambers. 2000. âSelf-Selection of the Analgesic Drug Carprofen by Lame Broiler Chickens.â Veterinary Record 146 (11): 307--11.
De Briyne, Nancy, Charlotte Berg, Thomas Blaha, and DĂ©borah Temple. 2016. âPig Castration: Will the Eu Manage to Ban Pig Castration by 2018?â Porcine Health Management 2: 1--11.
Dunlop, Rebecca, Sarah Millsopp, and Peter Laming. 2006. âAvoidance Learning in Goldfish (Carassius Auratus) and Trout (Oncorhynchus Mykiss) and Implications for Pain Perception.â Applied Animal Behaviour Science 97 (2): 255--71. https://ââdoi.org/ââhttps://ââdoi.org/ââ10.1016/ââj.applanim.2005.06.018
Edsinger, Eric, and GĂŒl Dölen. 2018. âA Conserved Role for Serotonergic Neurotransmission in Mediating Social Behavior in Octopus.â Current Biology 28 (19): 3136--42.
Epley, Nicholas, and Thomas Gilovich. 2016. âThe Mechanics of Motivated Reasoning.â Journal of Economic Perspectives 30 (3): 133--40.
Faccin, Jamil EG, Fernanda Laskoski, Luciana F Hernig, Rafael Kummer, Gustavo FR Lima, Uislei AD Orlando, MĂĄrcio AD Gonçalves, Ana Paula G Mellagi, Rafael R Ulguim, and Fernando P Bortolozzo. 2020. âImpact of Increasing Weaning Age on Pig Performance and Belly Nosing Prevalence in a Commercial Multisite Production System.â Journal of Animal Science 98 (4): skaa031.
Fischer, Bob. 2022. Rethink Priorities. https://âârethinkpriorities.org/ââresearch-area/ââthe-welfare-range-table/ââ.
Fischer, Bob, and Andy Lamey. 2018. âField Deaths in Plant Agriculture.â Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31: 409--28.
Gallet, Craig A. 2010. âMeat Meets Meta: A Quantitative Review of the Price Elasticity of Meat.â American Journal of Agricultural Economics 92 (1): 258--72.
------. 2012. âA Meta-Analysis of the Price Elasticity of Meat: Evidence of Regional Differences.â Business and Economic Research 2 (2).
Gerber, Bertram, Ayse Yarali, Sören Diegelmann, Carsten T Wotjak, Paul Pauli, and Markus Fendt. 2014. âPain-Relief Learning in Flies, Rats, and Man: Basic Research and Applied Perspectives.â Learning & Memory 21 (4): 232--52.
Gottardo, Flaviana, E Nalon, Barbara Contiero, S Normando, P Dalvit, and Giulio Cozzi. 2011. âThe Dehorning of Dairy Calves: Practices and Opinions of 639 Farmers.â Journal of Dairy Science 94 (11): 5724--34.
Govoni, Camilla, Davide Danilo Chiarelli, Alice Luciano, Matteo Ottoboni, Simge Nur Perpelek, Luciano Pinotti, and Maria Cristina Rulli. 2021. âGlobal Assessment of Natural Resources for Chicken Production.â Advances in Water Resources 154: 103987.
Hayes, Dave J, and Georg Northoff. 2011. âIdentifying a Network of Brain Regions Involved in Aversion-Related Processing: A Cross-Species Translational Investigation.â Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 49.
------. 2012. âCommon Brain Activations for Painful and Non-Painful Aversive Stimuli.â Bmc Neuroscience 13: 1--18.
Huemer, Michael. 2019. Dialogues on Ethical Vegetarianism. Routledge.
Korsgaard, Christine M. 2018. Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals. Oxford University Press.
Kuenzel, WJ. 2007. âNeurobiological Basis of Sensory Perception: Welfare Implications of Beak Trimming.â Poultry Science 86 (6): 1273--82.
Lambert, Helen, Amelia Cornish, Angie Elwin, and Neil DâCruze. 2022. âA Kettle of Fish: A Review of the Scientific Literature for Evidence of Fish Sentience.â Animals 12 (9): 1182.
Lear, Jonathan. 1988. Aristotle: The Desire to Understand. Cambridge University Press.
Lewis, Danny. 2016. âNew Way to Wean Calves Leaves Them Happier and Healthier.â Smithsonian Magazine, January. https://ââwww.smithsonianmag.com/ââsmart-news/âânew-way-wean-calves-leaves-them-happier-healthier-180957919/ââ.
Loughnan, Steve, Nick Haslam, and Brock Bastian. 2010. âThe Role of Meat Consumption in the Denial of Moral Status and Mind to Meat Animals.â Appetite 55 (1): 156--59.
Mekonnen, Mesfin M, Christopher MU Neale, Chittaranjan Ray, Galen E Erickson, and Arjen Y Hoekstra. 2019. âWater Productivity in Meat and Milk Production in the Us from 1960 to 2016.â Environment International 132: 105084.
Nogueira, BRF, MP Reis, AC Carvalho, EAC Mendoza, BL Oliveira, VA Silva, and AG Bertechini. 2019. âPerformance, Growth Curves and Carcass Yield of Four Strains of Broiler Chicken.â Brazilian Journal of Poultry Science 21 (04): eRBCA--2018.
Pinel, John P, Michael J Mana, and JâAnne A Ward. 1989. âStretched-Approach Sequences Directed at a Localized Shock Source by Rattus Norvegicus.â Journal of Comparative Psychology 103 (2): 140.
Pinker, Steven. 2011. The Better Angels of Our Nature: The Decline of Violence in History and Its Causes. Penguin UK.
Regan, Tom. 1983. âThe Case for Animal Rights.â
Ritchie, Hannah. 2023. âHow Many Animals Are Factory-Farmed?â Our World in Data.
Rosenfeld, Daniel L. 2018. âThe Psychology of Vegetarianism: Recent Advances and Future Directions.â Appetite 131: 125--38.
Rushen, J, and P Congdon. 1986. âSheep May Be More Averse to Electro-Immobilisation than to Shearing.â
Scruton, Roger. 1996. Animal Rights and Wrongs. Demos.
Scully, Matthew. 2002. Dominion: The Power of Man, the Suffering of Animals, and the Call to Mercy. Macmillan.
Singer, Peter. 1975. âAnimal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals.â
Smith, Ewan St John, and Gary R Lewin. 2009. âNociceptors: A Phylogenetic View.â Journal of Comparative Physiology a 195: 1089--1106.
Sneddon, Lynne U., Robert W. Elwood, Shelley A. Adamo, and Matthew C. Leach. 2014. âDefining and Assessing Animal Pain.â Animal Behaviour 97: 201--12. https://ââdoi.org/ââhttps://ââdoi.org/ââ10.1016/ââj.anbehav.2014.09.007
Spain, C Victor, Daisy Freund, Heather Mohan-Gibbons, Robert G Meadow, and Laurie Beacham. 2018. âAre They Buying It? United States Consumersâ Changing Attitudes toward More Humanely Raised Meat, Eggs, and Dairy.â Animals 8 (8): 128.
Sporchia, Fabio, Ermias Kebreab, and Dario Caro. 2021. âAssessing the Multiple Resource Use Associated with Pig Feed Consumption in the European Union.â Science of the Total Environment 759: 144306.
Sutherland, Mhairi A, and Cassandra B Tucker. 2011. âThe Long and Short of It: A Review of Tail Docking in Farm Animals.â Applied Animal Behaviour Science 135 (3): 179--91.
Thompson, Barton A. 2024. âConcern for Animals among Hunter-Gatherers.â Cross-Cultural Research, 10693971241234109.
Trusts, Pew Charitable, and Johns Hopkins. 2008. âPutting Meat on the Table: Industrial Farm Animal Production in America.â A Report of the Pew Commission on Industrial Farm Animal Production, a Project of the Pew Charitable Trusts and Johns Hopkins Bloomberg School of Public Health.
Whittaker, Alexandra L, and Gordon S Howarth. 2014. âUse of Spontaneous Behaviour Measures to Assess Pain in Laboratory Rats and Mice: How Are We Progressing?â Applied Animal Behaviour Science 151: 1--12.
- â©ïž
A word of caution is in order. This FAQ represents my views and only my views. Many other vegetarians and vegans reached the same conclusion by different means or emphasising different arguments.
I do think it is better, when promoting vegetarianism, to focus on moral arguments around animal welfare rather than possible human health benefits. The main reason why is that the animal suffering is the thing that really matters, far more than any health benefit for humans. But also, there is some evidence that ethical vegetarians exclude more animal products from their diets, and are better able to sustain their diets, than health-motivated vegetarians (Rosenfeld 2018). The same goes for arguments around climate change. I think those are fragile because climate change isnât the thing that is most important here. Focusing on climate change can lead people to make choices (like switching from beef to chicken) that can help the climate but actually increase the total amount of animal suffering.
- â©ïž
This argument does not apply only to great moral catastrophes. It also applies, for example, to the development of the Atomic Bomb, which was thought, for a while, to have the potential for igniting the atmosphere. It turned out not to have been able to do that, but clearly the scientists involved were obliged to either reach a high degree of confidence that it could not, or to halt the Trinity test. They made some effort to determine the likelihood of such an event, and were reasonably confident that it could not happen. But perhaps even more confidence was warranted. Wikipedia:
Enrico Fermi offered to take wagers among the top physicists and military present on whether the atmosphere would ignite, and if so whether it would destroy just the state, or incinerate the entire planet. This last result had been previously calculated by Bethe to be almost impossible, although for a while it had caused some of the scientists some anxiety. Bainbridge was furious with Fermi for frightening the guards, some of whom asked to be relieved; his own biggest fear was that nothing at all would happen, in which case he would have to return to the tower to investigate.
Iâm not relying on the precautionary, risk-averse principle here. Iâm relying on simple expected value calculation. It clearly makes sense to avoid actions that are reasonably likely to cause tremendous harm, until and unless we are more confident that the probability that they cause harm is very small, or that the harm we expect may be caused is much smaller than we previously thought.
- â©ïž
Loughnan, Haslam, and Bastian (2010) randomly gave students either beef jerky or cashews and then asked them to judge the moral status of animals; participants who ate meat showed less concern for animals. That is only one study (N=108), but itâs the kind of effect that seems plausible to me on priors, given how common motivated reasoning is.
- â©ïž
According to the US Population Reference Bureau, about 117B people have ever lived on Earth.
- â©ïž
Each year, the EU produces 22M tonnes of pork, 6.6M tonnes of veal and beef and 13M tonnes of poultry. If a pig produces 75 kg of pork, thatâs 290M pigs slaughtered annually. If a cow (ignoring calves killed for veal) produces 270 kg of beef, thatâs 24M cows slaughtered annually. If a chicken produces 1.4 kg of meat, thatâs 9.3B chickens slaughtered annually.
- â©ïž
I had initially linked a video of a farmer dehorning a cow, but YouTube removed it due to its graphical content. Anyway, needless to say, it is not easy to watch. Cattle horns are filled with blood vessels and nerves, so it is not like cutting nails. It might feel something like having your teeth amputated at the root.
- â©ïž
To be more precise, only two federal laws regulate the treatment of farmed animals in the US. They are (1) the Twenty-Eight Hour Law which says that, if livestock are being transported >28 consecutive hours, they must be offloaded for at least five consecutive hours to get feed, water and rest, and (2) the Humane Methods of Slaughter Act which says that cattle, pigs and sheep (but not chicken, fish or other animals) must be rendered insensible to pain before being killed (Trusts and Hopkins 2008). Many states have animal cruelty laws, but those laws, which would make many common factory farming practices illegal, typically explicitly exclude farmed animals from consideration (Trusts and Hopkins 2008).
A few states ban some of the worst practices, but far from all, and most donât ban any. According to the Humane Society of the United States, as of 2024, 11â50 states ban gestation crates, 10â50 states ban veal crates, 11â50 states ban the use of cages for egg-laying hens, 3â50 states ban tail docking of cattle and California bans the production and sale of foie gras.
- â©ïž
For example, tail docking without anesthesia is illegal in the EU.
- â©ïž
My list focuses on Western schools of philosophy, since that is what I know better. Indian philosophy, and especially Buddhism, is often animal-friendly too. But I donât know what Islamic philosophy, Confucianism, Daoism and African schools of thought say about animals.
- â©ïžâ©ïž
For the US, dividing the previously mentioned total annual killings by the US population size gives 28 chickens, 0.4 pigs and 0.1 cows killed per capita per year. This is likely a somewhat conservative estimate for adults, given that it uses the entire population size, including a lot of children who eat less meat.
For fish and shrimp, I use FarmKindâs calculations. They seem to be fairly well calibrated with mineâmy calculation produced 28 chickens, 0.4 pigs and 0.1 cows per capita per year, similar to FarmKindâs 33 chickens, 0.4 pigs and 0.1 cows. FarmKind estimates the overall impact of an omnivore diet, meaning the difference between that and veganism, not vegetarianism. That likely makes little difference for fishes, shrimps, cows and pigs, which are primarily killed in meat production. But given that many chickens are killed in egg production, that could account for the discrepancy in the chicken estimates.
Another way to estimate chicken deaths prevented is using the annual consumption in weight. According to the USDA, 101.2 lbs of chicken are expected to be killed per capita in the US in 2024, each weighing an average of 6.54 lbs. When you process a chicken, you get about 80% of its live weight as usable meat (Nogueira et al. 2019). That means the average American eats 19 chickens per year. However, as FarmKind notes, many animals die prematurely on factory farms such that you need to raise more animals than just those that reach the plates. So the actual numbers may be closer to my chicken estimate of 28 per capita per year. (In the EU, 25 kg of chicken is consumed per capita each year, meaning 11 chickens naively.)
To get the EU numbers, I do the same procedureâdivide the total annual killings in the EU by the EU population sizeâas for the US. That gives 21 chickens, 0.6 pigs and 0.05 cows per capita per year.
- â©ïž
According to some panpsychist theories, rocks may have minds and may therefore in some sense be sentient. I do not subscribe to panpsychism, but if you do, I suppose you will agree that animals also have moral standing.
- â©ïž
Though those laws sometimes do not address farmed animals. For example, in the US, the Animal Welfare Act of 1966 explicitly excludes birds, lab rats and lab mice, cold-blooded animals and farm animals. You have to assume farm and lab animals were excluded not for any principled reason, but out of convenience, given how similar they are to mammals that were not excluded.
- â©ïž
For example, people in hunter-gatherer societies seem to often show less concern for animal welfare (Thompson 2024). Pinker (2011) recounts an interesting anecdote: âThat is perhaps the hardest part of being an anthropologist. They sensed my weakness and would sell me all kinds of baby animals with descriptions of what they would do to them otherwise. I used to take them far into the desert and release them, they would track them, and bring them back to me for sale again!â My impression is also that concern for animals is lower among the less educated, such that, with notable exceptions like India, it tends to be lower in non-Western countries.
- â©ïž
Could sentience have evolved suddenly, say, at some point after we split from the other primates? That seems unlikely to me. One, most traits and capabilities seem to have evolved graduallyâthis is what we would expect from the process of natural selection. Two, to the extent that sentience is adaptive (e.g. by helping us respond appropriately to stimuli), partial sentience should also be partially adaptive. Being somewhat able to feel and perceive things is probably somewhat useful, if the ability to more fully feel and perceive things is useful. Three, the brain structures related to emotion and perception seem to have evolved gradually.
- â©ïž
A thought experiment. Suppose tomorrow we are able to genetically engineer a group of chimpanzees to possess above-human-level cognitive capabilities. Their DNA is distinct from ours, yet they develop a complex culture, create art and describe to us in our language what it is like to be a chimpanzee. They tell us that they can feel pain and discuss moral questions with great subtlety. They are not members of the human species, and still it would be prudent to treat them as individuals worthy of moral consideration.
- â©ïž
You might still have some uncertainty about the moral status of bivalves. Brian Tomasik concludes: âWhile bivalves are probably less sentient than most animals of their size, they still sense their environments, show altered morphine levels in response to trauma, and adjust to changing environmental conditions.â
- â©ïž
Dogs and pigs are similar in many morally relevant waysâboth are intelligent creatures capable of rich social and emotional lives. That is why dogs are also bred for food in some parts of the world, whereas pigs are also used as companion animals. The classification of dog as privileged companion animal and pig as farm animal surely springs at least partly from dogsâ usefulness for hunting, pest control and other labour and pigsâ meat yield. But itâs surely also partly a convention, given that both species show similar levels of intelligence, sociability and capacity for feeling. So our moral intuitions about animal sentience and suffering may be fundamentally compromised by economic and cultural factors rather than following consistent ethical principles.
The way we domesticated dogs and pigs probably shaped the way we conceive of them morally. Dogs, domesticated for hunting and protection, needed to be strong and alive to be useful. Pigs, domesticated for meat production, needed to be slaughtered. That must have incentivised us to view them differently, to soothe our consciences. There are many examples of convenience driving moral judgment, for example, Aristotle, a slave owner, concluding that some people, being better suited to physical than cognitive labour, are ânatural slavesâ, and that it is better for those people to be ruled by others (e.g. by Aristotle). (Though for a different take on Aristotleâs views on slavery, see Lear (1988).) It is possible that we first decided that boars and wolves should have different moral status, and only then set about domesticating these animals accordingly, but that seems unlikely to me.
- â©ïž
At least, it is wrong to kill humans for the reasons we typically kill animals. It can still be permissible to kill a human in self-defense, say, just as it can be permissible to kill an animal in self-defense.
- â©ïž
You might think something like: âHumans are uniquely impermissible to kill because we make plans for the future and value those futures, whereas the other animals merely act instinctively, living in the present. True, rats and squirrels plan for the future by hoarding food, but those are likely hardwired instinctive behaviours, not the result of higher-level plan-making. When you kill an animal, assuming it doesnât suffer in the moment, nothing is lost except whatever suffering and pleasure it might have experienced, had it gone on living.â I donât really buy this, because if I imagine a human who is somehow defective such that they are unable to make plans and value different futures, I still think it would be wrong to kill that human. I donât see why a creature needs to conceptualize its future to have present interests that deserve protection. If I recall correctly, this issue is discussed in Korsgaard (2018), though I donât have the book at hand and donât remember the details of the discussion.
- â©ïž
It is a separate, and I think irrelevant, question whether extinction of farmed animals would actually be bad for farmed animals. A cow likely does not care about the continued existence of its species, beyond immediate concerns like its own health and reproductive success. So for whom would a cow extinction event be bad? It would, perhaps, be bad for us, as we can take aesthetic pleasure in the continued existence of cows. For more on this issue, see Korsgaard (2018).
- â©ïž
Again, if we think that animals, like humans, matter morally, it is useful to consider what we would do if we swapped animals for humans. Imagine we could walk into a supermarket today and buy human meat, the human having been raised in an enclosure in a factory farmâliterally treated like an animal his or her entire lifeâand unceremoniously slaughtered for mere gustatory pleasure. I would not consider âbut when you buy the human meat, the human is already deadâ a convincing justification for buying human meat.
- â©ïž
The estimate is based on Saulius Simcikasâs research and Open Philanthropyâs subsequent adjustment.
- â©ïž
See earlier calculation.[10:1]
Good article. To add to your religious argument section, hereâs some info about Judaismâs stance on vegetarianism
Thanks for writing this upâitâs very comprehensive! (Also, broadly similar to my current thoughts.) Thereâs one argument meat eating might be okay (not an argument for âgoodâ) that I rarely see discussed explicitly, and Iâm wondering if you have thoughts on:
Whatâs the nature of moral responsibility vis a vis indirect consequences of your actions? You have the quote about being to blame for murder even if you hired an assassin rather than pulling the trigger yourselfâand this seems reasonable to me. But how about this intuition pump: it just so happens that, whenever my mailman comes by to deliver mail, he kicks the neighbors dog a few times. I am aware of this. I now order something delivered by mail. Am I responsible for the dog getting kicked?
Intuitively (not a moral philosopher, disclaimers apply, etc.), I want to say that Iâm not responsible. Even though the dog-kicking is a known consequence of my mail-getting,
I didnât kick the dog
I didnât want the dog to be kicked
The dog doesnât have to get kicked as a core part of getting mail delivered
I would be willing to pay more for my mail delivery if the dog were not kicked (to really torture the hypothetical, e.g. if the marginal non-sadistic mail carrier demanded slightly higher wages)
The correct âmoral fixâ isnât âdonât get mail,â itâs âdonât kick dogs.â Do you share this intuition of non-responsibility? Is meat eating somewhere between hiring an assassin (bad consequences are inherent in the act; actor to blame) and getting mail in this hypothetical (bad consequences not inherent in the act of getting mail; actor not to blame)? How do you think about âblameâ differently from âconsequentialist obligationâ?
But itâs possible to order mail without a dog being kicked. It is not possible (yet) to eat meat without an animal being killed. Itâs not eating the meat thatâs wrong, itâs killing the animal
Sure, cultured meat is for most intents and purposes not yet available. If you think most of the badness of meat eating is in the killing itself, the exact conditions under which the animal lived probably donât matter much to your decision making. But it is possible with current technology to eat an animal that has not been tortured, had a rich and pleasant life, etc. If you favor a [certain flavor of] utilitarian perspective, itâs possible to eat meat such that the animal being eaten had a net very good life.
So, suppose Iâm vaguely utilitarian but not a super strict consequentialist. How do I think about meat eating given that the marginal consumption causes lots of expected suffering, but the suffering is not a first order or desired consequence of my actions?
Great post, Erich!
Agreed.
Nicely written. Though my feeling with discussing why I am a vegetarian often shows that people are not really interested in knowing whatâs really going on. Perhaps being willingly ignorant can offer some sort of comfort.